An argument against Bohmian mechanics?

In summary: Simple systems can exhibit very different behavior from more complex systems with a large number of degrees of freedom. This is a well-known fact in physics. Thus, I don't understand why you keep bringing up the hydrogen atom as a counterexample to ergodic behavior, when it is not a representative system for such a discussion. In summary, Neumaier argues that Bohmian mechanics is wrong because it fails to predict all observed results from experiments. However, this argument ignores the theory of quantum measurements and fails to take into account the effect of measurement. Furthermore, the Bohmian theory of quantum measurements is incomplete and cannot fully explain the behavior of the single universe we know of. Additionally, the claim that ergodic theorem is necessary for
  • #246
vanhees71 said:
Then the question is, whether there's a reason for the universe to start in "quantum equilibrium" and not in another state. Of course, a lot about cosmology is pure speculation, like the puzzle concerning the matter-antimatter asymmetry. It's always assumed that the universe started with a symmetric state (i.e., equal amount of matter and antimatter), but that's an assumption (although a pretty "natural" one). Also inflation is an ad-hoc assumption to solve some puzzles like the flatness and horizon problems, but it's in no way verified today by observations.

The universe should not start in quantum equilibium, however, under certain dynamics, equilibrium can be rapidly reached - so BM makes QM analogous to statistical mechanics.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #247
Is there anything in BM that can disturb the quantum equilibrium?
 
  • #248
vanhees71 said:
Again, I don't understand this. The Born rule is applied everywhere, where QT is applied to describe observed phenomena. Nobody talks about a cut. You have some preparation procedure (e.g., the bunches of protons running in the LHC) and measurement devices (e.g., the big detectors ATLAS, CMS, LHCb, and ALICE). Then as much "statistics" is taken as possible (i.e., you make a lot of pp collisions at the LHC energy and observe a lot of things with the detectors to measure spectra, cross sections, etc. etc.). I don't need new artificial words like beable or the like. Physics is just what's done in the lab, the evaluation of the data by experimentalists and the description (aka modeling/simulating) in terms of QT by theoreticians.

Who is "nobody"? Landau and Lifshitz? Weinberg? I hate to argue from authority, but you are simply wrong that nobody talks about a cut when two of the most distinguished quantum mechanics textbooks mention it.
 
  • #249
ShayanJ said:
Is there anything in BM that can disturb the quantum equilibrium?

Quantum equilibrium is analogous to thermodynamic equilibrium, so yes, it can be disturbed.
 
  • #250
atyy said:
Quantum equilibrium is analogous to thermodynamic equilibrium, so yes, it can be disturbed.
Technological limits aside, can you think of any experimental setup that is able to probe quantum non-equilibrium?
 
  • #251
vanhees71 said:
Hm, out of curiosity of course, but when I can't check my ideas experimentally, I'm not doing of much value for science.
Then, by the same token, I think about Bohmian mechanics out of curiosity too, with the same caveat on the value for science. So whenever someone tells you that he likes to think about BM, just tell yourself: "Aaa, I get it, that's not really science but just curiosity, the same thing I am doing when I think about magic tricks.:woot: "
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #252
atyy said:
Quantum equilibrium is analogous to thermodynamic equilibrium, so yes, it can be disturbed.
Unless the whole universe is in the equilibrium, in which case the disturbance is only possible as a small-probability fluctuation.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #253
atyy said:
Who is "nobody"? Landau and Lifshitz? Weinberg? I hate to argue from authority, but you are simply wrong that nobody talks about a cut when two of the most distinguished quantum mechanics textbooks mention it.
Well, where in these books is this idea ever really used, and where is it necessary to be used? I just take a measurement apparatus and measure something. I don't need a cut to use it to check the predictions of quantum theory.
 
  • #254
vanhees71 said:
Well, where in these books is this idea ever really used, and where is it necessary to be used? I just take a measurement apparatus and measure something. I don't need a cut to use it to check the predictions of quantum theory.

They use it when they do not include the measurement apparatus in the quantum state.
 
  • #255
As someone who likes to explain magic tricks, I still find the comparison to BM a bit outrageous. It's a terrible analogy. If your explanation requires invisible pink unicorns that are spread over the whole universe and need to conspire over cosmic distances in order to make the rabbit appear, then I would reject the explanation immediately, even though I would have to admit that technically, it's not excluded by observations. Just because something is an explanation, it doesn't mean it's a rational explanation. BM is possibly one of the least rational explanations that people have come up with in the history of science.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #256
atyy said:
They use it when they do not include the measurement apparatus in the quantum state.
Where concretely use my experimenter colleagues the cut when they analyze an experiment at the LHC? As far as I now they use a data file provided by the detectors, which are real-world measurement devices to register particles. The corresponding outcomes of measurements are compared to the (probabilistic) predictions of quantum theory. Nowhere do they need to assume a cut to design their experiments and evaluate the data in terms of cross sections, predicted by QT.
 
  • #257
For experimentalists the location of the cut is unimportant. There is a mathematical formalism that wraps up the whole thing. That said it is most unsatisfying if you believe there is cut. The model doesn't distinguish between states pre and post cut as far as I can tell, making our formulaism a shorthand.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #258
vanhees71 said:
Where concretely use my experimenter colleagues the cut when they analyze an experiment at the LHC? As far as I now they use a data file provided by the detectors, which are real-world measurement devices to register particles. The corresponding outcomes of measurements are compared to the (probabilistic) predictions of quantum theory. Nowhere do they need to assume a cut to design their experiments and evaluate the data in terms of cross sections, predicted by QT.

Concretely, the cut is used when they claim to have made an observation. You can tell they have made a cut if they claim certain observations are consistent with quantum mechanics, and they have used the Born rule.
 
  • #259
rubi said:
As someone who likes to explain magic tricks, I still find the comparison to BM a bit outrageous. It's a terrible analogy. If your explanation requires invisible pink unicorns that are spread over the whole universe and need to conspire over cosmic distances in order to make the rabbit appear, then I would reject the explanation immediately, even though I would have to admit that technically, it's not excluded by observations. Just because something is an explanation, it doesn't mean it's a rational explanation. BM is possibly one of the least rational explanations that people have come up with in the history of science.

But you like Consistent Histories, which means your dislike of BM is only a matter of tase - unlike vanhees71, which is a technical disagreement. If we apply vanhees71's view, Consistent Histories is also pointless.
 
  • #260
ShayanJ said:
Technological limits aside, can you think of any experimental setup that is able to probe quantum non-equilibrium?

Valentini has done some work on this, but it has limitations that were discussed by Demystifier in his posts above.

Anyway, the basic idea is that unless there is fine tuning, it is unlikely the universe was created in equilibrium. If the universe was created in non-equilibrium, there may still be some signatures of that nonequilibrium observable today.
 
  • #261
atyy said:
But you like Consistent Histories, which means your dislike of BM is only a matter of tase - unlike vanhees71, which is a technical disagreement. If we apply vanhees71's view, Consistent Histories is also pointless.
Can you summarize, what Consistent Histories claims beyond the minimal interpretation? Perhaps, I'm too pragmatic to realize, where the problem with the minimal interpretation is, but I just don't get, why it should help to introduce any elements of interpretation that go beyond Born's rule, which establishes the meaning of the formalism concerning observable (and observed!) facts about nature.
 
  • #262
atyy said:
Concretely, the cut is used when they claim to have made an observation. You can tell they have made a cut if they claim certain observations are consistent with quantum mechanics, and they have used the Born rule.
I still don't understand, where the cut is made. Experimentalists measure something by repeating for many times a preparation and measurement procedure and then analyze the experiment statistically. That's the way you "test hypotheses" in the sense of probability theory, and QT is just a probability theory for physical processes in nature, not more not less. There's no quantum-classical cut used anywhere. Also the construction of most measurement devices are based on QT nowadays since most are based on semiconductor technology, which is based on condensed-matter many-body QT. In other words, there is no clear boundary between classical behavior of macroscopic objects and quantum behavior of microscopic ones. The former is a more or less applicable approximation of the latter to describe macroscopic ("relevant") observables. It's no fundamental cut, but the application of an approximation.

Nobody talks about any "cut" when one uses non-relativistic approximations in classical mechanics or electrodynamics. There the non-relativistic treatment is a more or less applicable approximation to the fully relativistic one. That's the usual structure of physical theories: Different models or theories that are successful in describing certain phenomena can be approximations of each other. The more comprehensive theory tells us the range of validity of the approximations. The same holds for QT vs. classical approximations.

Historically the cut is due to the Heisenberg flavor of the Copenhagen interpretation and enters the game only because of the collapse hypothesis, which in my opinion is as superfluous and misleading as the introduction of a cut.
 
  • #263
vanhees71 said:
I still don't understand, where the cut is made. Experimentalists measure something by repeating for many times a preparation and measurement procedure and then analyze the experiment statistically. That's the way you "test hypotheses" in the sense of probability theory, and QT is just a probability theory for physical processes in nature, not more not less. There's no quantum-classical cut used anywhere.

Yes, there is. The probabilities occur in quantum mechanics (or QFT) in the form of the Born rule:

When you perform a measurement on a system, the result is one of the eigenvalues of the corresponding operator and the probability of an outcome is the square of the amplitude for the system to be in the corresponding eigenstate.

The use of probabilities involves a cut: You can describe it in several different ways:
  1. The cut between the system, which is the thing being measured, and the observer, which is the thing being measured.
  2. The cut between ordinary interactions, which are described by terms appearing in the Hamiltonian, and measurements, which are described by the Born rule. The system evolves smoothly and deterministically according to Hamiltonian dynamics in response to ordinary interactions, but measurements behave probabilistically.
  3. The cut between microscopic systems, which are described by quantum amplitudes and which can be in superpositions of drastically different states, and macroscopic systems, which are observed to always have approximately definite values for quantities such as position. (By "approximately definite", let me illustrate by example: An automobile's position is subject to imprecision--you can't really say where it is with a precision much greater than the size of the automobile. But you would never say that it is uncertain whether an automobile is in London or New York City. So to within the limits of precision, its location is definite.)
To apply the Born rule, you must declare some aspect of the universe to be on the observer/measurement/macroscopic side of the cut.

This seems obvious to me. Certainly, if you consider two electrons interacting, does it make any sense to say that one electron is measuring the z-component of the spin of the other electron? Obviously not. The two electrons interact, and that interaction might depend on their spins, but there is never a point where one electron can be said to have measured the spin of the other. The Born rule can only be applied if there is a system that is macroscopic, that is capable of forming permanent records of past interactions. So it requires a "cut" between those parts of the universe that are treated using (reversible) microscopic dynamics and those parts that involve irreversible changes during a measurement interaction. If the measurement device is described by reversible dynamics, then there is nowhere to apply the Born rule.
 
  • #264
But the interactions described by QT are the interactions between the measured object and the measurement apparatus, or at least there's no hint that only because something is constructed by men as a measurement device, all of a sudden different than the fundamental interactions described by QT are at work. This reminds me somehow at the old idea that there's a special "vis viva" at work disinguishing natural laws valid for living organisms vs. non-living matter (even there it's hard to clearly define a boundary, e.g., are viruses or prions living beings or not). That macroscopic devices are able to store information about the measured quantum system doesn't imply that there are other physical laws at work as those described by the Standard Model, i.e., QT.
 
  • #265
It seems to me the discussion about the Heisenberg cut is not about its existence in the theory, but about whether that is a problem or not.
The cut is inherent to the construction of QM theory and in simple terms consists of the non-debatable coexistence in the formalism of classical observables and quantum probabilities per the Born rule. Whether one considers this a problem for the theory or just accepts it naturally like vanhees does should be a personal conclusion, not a source of dispute.
 
Last edited:
  • #266
vanhees71 said:
But the interactions described by QT are the interactions between the measured object and the measurement apparatus,

But the additional rule, that a measurement result only results in an eigenvalue, with probabilities given by the square of the amplitude, applies only to measurements. So if you have a rule that only applies to some kinds of interactions, and not others, then you have a cut. You certainly can't apply that rule to the interaction between two electrons; you can't say that one electron is measuring something about the other electron, and will get such and such a result with such and such a probability.

What von Neumann first noted was that you can always move the cut to enlarge the part of the universe that is on the "microscopic" side, but you can't eliminate it. Without the cut, you don't have the Born rule. If you analyzed everything using microscopic dynamics, then there is suddenly no role for probabilities (unless the people trying to derive probabilities for Many Worlds succeed).
 
  • Like
Likes RockyMarciano
  • #267
Also IMO the cut doesn't exist in nature, just in the QM formalism. In BM (and in MWI) the cut in the formalism is taken as real, and so it needs to build a classical ontology coexisting with the quantum phenomenology.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #268
RockyMarciano said:
It seems to me the discussion about the Heisenberg cut is not about its existence in the theory, but about whethertthat is a problem or not.
The cut is inherent to the construction of QM theory and in simple terms consists of the non-debatable coexistence in the formalism of classical observables and quantum probabilities per the Born rule. Whether one considers this a problem for the theory or just accepts it naturally like vanhees does should be a personal conclusion, not a source of dispute.

You can certainly say, as Von Neumann did, that there are two kinds of interactions: normal interactions that are described by Schrodinger's equation (or quantum field theory), and measurement interactions that involve a discontinuous change to a system. That's ugly, but it's coherent. What seems incoherent to me is accepting the practical advantages to the two types of interaction while also denying that there is anything special about measurement. That seems inconsistent, not just a matter of personal taste.
 
  • #269
RockyMarciano said:
Also IMO the cut doesn't exist in nature, just in the QM formalism. In BM (and in MWI) the cut in the formalism is taken as real, and so it needs to build a classical ontology coexisting with the quantum phenomenology.

Yes, but if the cut exists only in the formalism, that suggests (to me) that its appearance is due to not having the formalism figured out completely. Something analogous might be Special Relativity. The elegant way that SR is taught today makes no reference to a preferred rest frame. However, you can imagine an alternate history in which Einstein never came along, and we were stuck with an ad-hoc theory in which there is a preferred reference frame such that:
  • In that frame, light travels at speed [itex]c[/itex] in all directions.
  • Clocks (and other systems that change internal state with time) moving relative to this frame run slower.
  • Physical objects moving relative to this frame are contracted in the direction of their motion.
You can make such an ad hoc theory to be observationally equivalent to SR, but you're stuck with an unobservable preferred rest frame. People could then speculate that this is only needed for the formalism, but isn't really part of nature.
 
  • Like
Likes kurt101 and Jilang
  • #270
stevendaryl said:
You can certainly say, as Von Neumann did, that there are two kinds of interactions: normal interactions that are described by Schrodinger's equation (or quantum field theory), and measurement interactions that involve a discontinuous change to a system. That's ugly, but it's coherent. What seems incoherent to me is accepting the practical advantages to the two types of interaction while also denying that there is anything special about measurement. That seems inconsistent, not just a matter of personal taste.
Agreed. It is nevertheless an inconsistence that doesn't bother experimentalists(and a certain theorist which appears to have an experimentalist soul ;-)) in their applying the theory and it is no use trying to make them feel the inconsistence.
 
  • #271
RockyMarciano said:
Agreed. It is nevertheless an inconsistence that doesn't bother experimentalists(and a certain theorist which appears to have an experimentalist soul ) in their applying the theory and it is no use trying to make them feel the inconsistence.

I have to agree. Logically, the appearance of an inconsistency is a catastrophe, because in an inconsistent system, you can prove anything. But practically, people can live perfectly well with an inconsistency, they just learn how to step around it without stepping into it (so to speak).
 
  • #272
stevendaryl said:
Yes, but if the cut exists only in the formalism, that suggests (to me) that its appearance is due to not having the formalism figured out completely. Something analogous might be Special Relativity. The elegant way that SR is taught today makes no reference to a preferred rest frame. However, you can imagine an alternate history in which Einstein never came along, and we were stuck with an ad-hoc theory in which there is a preferred reference frame such that:
  • In that frame, light travels at speed [itex]c[/itex] in all directions.
  • Clocks (and other systems that change internal state with time) moving relative to this frame run slower.
  • Physical objects moving relative to this frame are contracted in the direction of their motion.
You can make such an ad hoc theory to be observationally equivalent to SR, but you're stuck with an unobservable preferred rest frame. People could then speculate that this is only needed for the formalism, but isn't really part of nature.
Well, you still have people harping on with the ether.
 
  • #273

stevendaryl said:
Yes, but if the cut exists only in the formalism, that suggests (to me) that its appearance is due to not having the formalism figured out completely. Something analogous might be Special Relativity. The elegant way that SR is taught today makes no reference to a preferred rest frame. However, you can imagine an alternate history in which Einstein never came along, and we were stuck with an ad-hoc theory in which there is a preferred reference frame such that:
  • In that frame, light travels at speed [itex]c[/itex] in all directions.
  • Clocks (and other systems that change internal state with time) moving relative to this frame run slower.
  • Physical objects moving relative to this frame are contracted in the direction of their motion.
You can make such an ad hoc theory to be observationally equivalent to SR, but you're stuck with an unobservable preferred rest frame. People could then speculate that this is only needed for the formalism, but isn't really part of nature.
I didn't calibrate the content of this in my previous response, it is a deep reflection. Bit it leads to doubt about the formalism.
 
  • #274
stevendaryl said:
But the additional rule, that a measurement result only results in an eigenvalue, with probabilities given by the square of the amplitude, applies only to measurements. So if you have a rule that only applies to some kinds of interactions, and not others, then you have a cut. You certainly can't apply that rule to the interaction between two electrons; you can't say that one electron is measuring something about the other electron, and will get such and such a result with such and such a probability.

What von Neumann first noted was that you can always move the cut to enlarge the part of the universe that is on the "microscopic" side, but you can't eliminate it. Without the cut, you don't have the Born rule. If you analyzed everything using microscopic dynamics, then there is suddenly no role for probabilities (unless the people trying to derive probabilities for Many Worlds succeed).
Of course, these are part of the postulates of QT, but it doesn't imply that there is a distinct classical world or that the measurement is outside of the laws described by QT. There are no extra rules. Observables are in the formalism represented by self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space, and possible values these observables take when measured are the eigenvalues of these operators. This is formalism, but not a cut between quantum and classical laws. I also don't see, why it shouldn't be impossible to measure one electron with help of another electron. In the Stern-Gerlach experiment you measure a spin state even by the position of the particle itself. The Born rule is another independent postulate, but it also implies no cut. It just says how to evaluate probabilities for the outcomes of measurements given the state of the system. I don't understand your last sentence. Why isn't there any probablities if I analyze everything using microscopic dynamics? The microscopic dynamics, i.e., QT, describes probabilities and only probabilities. What else should the meaning of this dynamics be than the time evolution of probability distributions for observables?
 
  • #275
stevendaryl said:
But the additional rule, that a measurement result only results in an eigenvalue, with probabilities given by the square of the amplitude, applies only to measurements. So if you have a rule that only applies to some kinds of interactions, and not others, then you have a cut. You certainly can't apply that rule to the interaction between two electrons; you can't say that one electron is measuring something about the other electron, and will get such and such a result with such and such a probability.

OK, that is pretty clear. So if these electrons interact, we can calculate the amplitudes of various outcomes but we cannot ( or should not) square these amplitudes to get probabilities ? I'm a bit confused, as you can see.
 
  • #276
The "amplitudes" are not observable according to standard QT, the probabilities are (on ensembles of accordingly prepared systems)!
 
  • #277
vanhees71 said:
I still don't understand, where the cut is made. Experimentalists measure something by repeating for many times a preparation and measurement procedure and then analyze the experiment statistically. That's the way you "test hypotheses" in the sense of probability theory, and QT is just a probability theory for physical processes in nature, not more not less. There's no quantum-classical cut used anywhere. Also the construction of most measurement devices are based on QT nowadays since most are based on semiconductor technology, which is based on condensed-matter many-body QT. In other words, there is no clear boundary between classical behavior of macroscopic objects and quantum behavior of microscopic ones. The former is a more or less applicable approximation of the latter to describe macroscopic ("relevant") observables. It's no fundamental cut, but the application of an approximation.

Nobody talks about any "cut" when one uses non-relativistic approximations in classical mechanics or electrodynamics. There the non-relativistic treatment is a more or less applicable approximation to the fully relativistic one. That's the usual structure of physical theories: Different models or theories that are successful in describing certain phenomena can be approximations of each other. The more comprehensive theory tells us the range of validity of the approximations. The same holds for QT vs. classical approximations.

Historically the cut is due to the Heisenberg flavor of the Copenhagen interpretation and enters the game only because of the collapse hypothesis, which in my opinion is as superfluous and misleading as the introduction of a cut.

In classical mechanics, eg. general relativity, there is no problem with the notion of the state of the universe. In quantum mechanics, what is the meaning of the quantum state of the universe?
 
  • #278
vanhees71 said:
The "amplitudes" are not observable according to standard QT, the probabilities are (on ensembles of accordingly prepared systems)!
That's exactly what @stevendaryl means(correct me if I'm wrong!). The dynamics of a quantum system only involves probability amplitudes and if no one wants to know anything about the system, no probability comes into play. So a unified description of all phenomena using quantum mechanics, can't involve axioms about probabilities because if all things that happen are governed by quantum mechanics, we should be able to treat measurements with the same language that we treat Schrodinger evolution. The fact that we have to introduce Born's rule to deal with measurements is the Heisenberg cut. Of course you may say that its ridiculous to apply quantum mechanics to macroscopic objects because it'll be unnecessarily complicated and that's why we introduce the Born's rule. But that viewpoint can only be true if you can derive Born's rule from the regular dynamics of quantum systems and that's what all these interpretations are all about. Of course decoherence makes things better for this viewpoint but I'm not sure we can count on it to solve the problem completely. Can we?
 
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #279
vanhees71 said:
The "amplitudes" are not observable according to standard QT, the probabilities are (on ensembles of accordingly prepared systems)!
I mean use the theory to get predictions using amplitudes !
 
  • #280
atyy said:
But you like Consistent Histories, which means your dislike of BM is only a matter of tase - unlike vanhees71, which is a technical disagreement. If we apply vanhees71's view, Consistent Histories is also pointless.
I don't think it's just a matter of taste to reject Bohmian mechanics. I think the situation is comparable to the epicycle theory. People just couldn't imagine that the Earth might not be in the center of the universe, so they had to come up with contrieved explanations for the motion of the planets. Bohmian mechanics is very similar: People don't want to give up the naive idealization that particles can be modeled as points in ##\mathbb R^3##, so they have to invent absurd mechanisms in order to maintain this idealization. Rationally, there is just no good reason for why nature could be mapped to points in ##\mathbb R^3## (especially if you recognize that ##\mathbb R^3## is just a mathematical object, whose properties depend on the choice of the underlying set theory axioms). It's just an idealization, whose domain of applicability is exceeded in the quantum regime. Progress in science depends on recognizing wrong ideas and replacing them by something better. Adhering to wrong ideas has never led to scientific progress and indeed, I'm not aware of a single relevant discovery that has emerged from Bohmian mechanics. On the other hand, great advances (such as QFT and the standard model) were made by taking the quantum formalism seriously. If the only positive thing that can be said about a theory is that it is not technically excluded by observations, then it's pretty clear that it is a dead end.

From reading vanhees' posts, I think he is secretly a consistent histories advocate without knowing it yet.

vanhees71 said:
Can you summarize, what Consistent Histories claims beyond the minimal interpretation? Perhaps, I'm too pragmatic to realize, where the problem with the minimal interpretation is, but I just don't get, why it should help to introduce any elements of interpretation that go beyond Born's rule, which establishes the meaning of the formalism concerning observable (and observed!) facts about nature.
Consistent histories is essentially the minimal interpretation stated with more conceptual clarity. It keeps all the concepts from Copenhagen, but it interprets time evolution as a stochastic process, much like classical Brownian motion. The insertion projection operators between the time evolution doesn't correspond to any physical process. Instead, it just selects a subset of histories from the path space, whose probability of occurring is to be calculated. It's completely analogous to the insertion of characteristic functions in the case of Brownian motion. No explicit references to measurements remain and all quantum paradoxes are resolved.

In Brownian motion, the Wiener measure on the space of Brownian paths is constructed by specifying it on so called cylinder sets of paths ##x(t)##:
$$O^{t_1 t_2 \ldots}_{B_1 B_2 \ldots}=\{x : x(t_1)\in B_1, x(t_2) \in B_2, \ldots \}$$
For example, the probability for a path (with ##x(t_0)=x_0##) to be in the cylinder set ##O^{t_1 t_2}_{B_1 B_2}## is (up to some normalization factors) given by
$$P(O^{t_1 t_2}_{B_1 B_2})=\int dx_2 dx_1 \chi_{B_2}(x_2) e^{-\frac{(x_2-x_1)^2}{t_2-t_1}} \chi_{B_1}(x_1) e^{-\frac{(x_1-x_0)^2}{t_1-t_0}} \hat = \lVert P_{B_2} U(t_2-t_1) P_{B_1} U(t_1-t_0)\delta_{x_0 t_0}\rVert$$
Here, I have defined the projections ##(P_B f)(x)=\chi_B(x) f(x)## and the time evolution operators ##U(t)=e^{-t\Delta}##, which are just expressed as integrations against the heat kernel in the above integral. Of course, nobody would think of the projectors ##P_B## as a form of time evolution in the totally classical case of Brownian motion. The Brownian particle just follows some random path and the the probability for a given set of paths just happens to involve this projector.

In quantum mechanics, the situation is completely analogous. The projectors of the position operator ##\hat x## are also given by characteristic functions ##\chi_B(x)## and the time evolution of the Schrödinger equation (for example for the free particle) is given by ##U(t)=e^{-it\frac{\Delta}{2m}}##. This suggests in a very compelling way that the projections are not "a different form of time evolution", like the Copenhagen interpretation suggests. Measurements don't play any distinguished role.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71, Mentz114 and dextercioby

Similar threads

Back
Top