- #36
- 8,218
- 1,942
PeterDonis said:a. None of this means the MWI does not have to account for the experimental results. Of course it does, just as any QM interpretation does. It just doesn't do it by appealing to "mutual influences" or "remote changes".
a. Again: once someone explains how nonlocal effects are made to happen using purely local mechanisms, I can determine this for myself. But without that, I can't agree with you.PeterDonis said:b. It does it by, first, saying that the wave function is all there is; second, saying that there is no collapse, so all of the possibilities contained in the wave function actually exist (meaning that measurements don't have single results--all possible results happen); and third, saying that the wave function is what enforces the correlations such as are observed in Bell inequality violations, entanglement swapping, etc.
b. All possible results occur, that's exactly the problem! QM precisely predicts a) some results NEVER happen; and b) some results occur far more or far less than I would expect from MWI. Neither of these are ever explained in a detail example.
I have requested a detail explanation of a specific referenced experiment above, and I believe there is a reader who follows MWI closely enough to walk me through the logic of that example. Specifically:
Photons 1 and 4 share no common past and are distant. A equally remote observer can choose to entangle them or not. How is it that if all outcomes are possible, we always see perfect correlations when those photons are measured at the same angle settings? And in fact Photon 1 can be measured BEFORE the remote observer chooses to entangle it with Photon 4, and even before the measurement setting for Photon 4 is selected? (Keeping in mind here that the same mechanism must also produce Bell inequalities when the angle setting are different.)
And of course I am really asking how this is accomplished through some hypothetical local mechanism.