- #36
Mentz114
- 5,432
- 292
Well, obviously I can't answer that.stevendaryl said:Huh?
Well, obviously I can't answer that.stevendaryl said:Huh?
Mentz114 said:Well, obviously I can't answer that.
The laws of physics are not written in terms of probabilities. Otherwise [itex]F=ma[/itex] has no meaning.
If you insist on that I cannot argue, obviously.
I'm sorry maybe I skipped too quickly there.stevendaryl said:I meant that I could not make any sense of your response:
I wasn't insisting on anything in particular, and I certainly wasn't saying that Newtonian physics is written in terms of probability. So I have no idea what prompted that response.
Mentz114 said:The laws of physics are not written in terms of probabilities.
Mentz114 said:Otherwise ##F=ma## has no meaning.
Mentz114 said:What do you think is the relationship between 'the rules of quantum theory' and the laws of physics ?
Fair enough. The governing principles of physical theories are conservation laws which are expressed mathematically as invariance of predictions under groups of transformations. Extremized paths in phase/configuration spaces are made from infinitessimal motions which are compounds of the generators of the groups.PeterDonis said:You should answer this since you were the one who introduced the term "the laws of physics". What did you mean by that term?
Mentz114 said:Fair enough. The governing principles of physical theories are conservation laws which are expressed mathematically as invariance of predictions under groups of transformations. Extremized paths in phase/configuration spaces are made from infinitessimal motions which are compounds of the generators of the groups.
I would call these things the LoP for the this discussion.
This is true of classical and quantum theories. The difference is in the Lie algebras of the group generators. In the quantum model the generators do not always commute ( or as Ballentine puts it ) there is indetereminacy ( a kind of ignorance). Actual classical objects (measuring instruments) also have some indeterminacy but are closer to the limiting case ( see my first post) than they are to the microscopic case.
This is why I do not believe that we are treating the measurement problem in a controversial way by asserting that the process is merely one in which amplification and filtering reduces the indeterminacy to make an outcome irreversible.
I reciprocate those feelings, so I'll let it be. It's not important.stevendaryl said:Your notion of what physics is about is so completely different from mine that I can't really relate them. .
stevendaryl said:Your notion of what physics is about is so completely different from mine that I can't really relate them. Conservation laws, symmetry principles, transformations, etc., are tools to be used in physics, but they aren't physics.
Is that not the same thing as trying to find some laws of physics. If you find some theory that agrees with experiment and applies to nearly all cases - is that a law ?stevendaryl said:To me, physics is: I observe something in the world around me. I come up with a model to describe what I observe. I test that model by seeing what other consequences it has, and seeing if those are born out by observation. If not, I get a new model, or modify the existing one. Repeat.
None of those things--symmetry, conservation, transformations, etc.---is fundamental to the project of physics, which is about describing the world that we live in in a way that is precise enough (mathematically) to make predictions capable of falsification.
Mentz114 said:We come back to your objection concerning the measurement problem. What law or principle that you hold is being dishonoured if we treat an apparatus as macroscopic ? None of my principles can be violated by any physical process, or any choice made by any agency at any time or place. Those are good principles.
With the slight rephrasing you've applied I agree in principle except I don't think the disconnect between the model we use for the macroscopic part and the model of the microscopic bit exists.stevendaryl said:I don't understand what you're talking about. The point I was making is that if a measurement apparatus is made up of electrons, protons, neutrons interacting through electromagnetic interactions, then it would seem to me that whatever rules for how those particles behave would logically imply everything there is know about how the measurement apparatus behaves. Conversely, if we have some rules about macroscopic measurement devices that does not follow from properties of electrons, protons, etc., then it seems to me that we have missed something in our modeling of the behavior of the latter.
I suppose you can take a completely phenomenological point of view, which is that the only things that are real are macroscopic objects, and electrons, protons, etc., are just mathematical fictions useful for calculating the behavior of the actual physical objects.
This is a very strange view. For me to figure out the symmetry principles (or any other general description of what we consider "fundamental laws of nature") is the very goal of what's called physics, which consists of both observations and theoretical mathematical analysis.stevendaryl said:Your notion of what physics is about is so completely different from mine that I can't really relate them. Conservation laws, symmetry principles, transformations, etc., are tools to be used in physics, but they aren't physics.
vanhees71 said:This is a very strange view. For me to figure out the symmetry principles (or any other general description of what we consider "fundamental laws of nature") is the very goal of what's called physics, which consists of both observations and theoretical mathematical analysis.
Measuring a microscopic system is due to the interaction with a macroscopic system which takes a well-defined macroscopic value for its pointer position,
Mentz114 said:With the slight rephrasing you've applied I agree in principle except I don't think the disconnect between the model we use for the macroscopic part and the model of the microscopic bit exists.
vanhees71 said:Further, according to our current understanding, the "classicality" of macroscopic systems (including measurement devices, which are nothing special but just also macroscopic systems) is well compatible with quantum theory and nothing else than the "Law of Large Numbers", i.e., if you have ##N## degrees microscopic degrees of freedom figuring additively into a macroscopic variable ##X## (like, e.g., the total energy of a gas which consists of ##N/3## monatomic particles) one has ##\Delta X/|X| \sim 1/\sqrt{N}##. If ##N## is large the fluctuations (both quantum an thermal) are small.
[my emphasis]stevendaryl said:I don't think that reasoning is correct. What you're suggesting is that the law of large numbers by itself is enough to explain why there are never macroscopic superpositions? The law of large numbers is only valid if you have a large number of independent systems with the same distribution of values of an observable, then the averages over all the systems will have a smaller variance than the values on the individual systems. But that's not what's going on when we perform a measurement and get a definite value.
The averaging is over a large number (of order ##10^24##) of microscopic observables making up a macroscopic one.stevendaryl said:I don't think that reasoning is correct. What you're suggesting is that the law of large numbers by itself is enough to explain why there are never macroscopic superpositions? The law of large numbers is only valid if you have a large number of independent systems with the same distribution of values of an observable, then the averages over all the systems will have a smaller variance than the values on the individual systems. But that's not what's going on when we perform a measurement and get a definite value.
stevendaryl said:None of those things--symmetry, conservation, transformations, etc.---is fundamental to the project of physics, which is about describing the world that we live in in a way that is precise enough (mathematically) to make predictions capable of falsification.
bhobba said:It's exactly what Feynman said - nothing more - nothing less:
However Noether provided an invaluable tool in making those 'guesses'.
What came first - the guess or its experimental proof? The logic of those guesses is sometimes so compelling you are shocked if it's wrong. Even Feynman realized it. He came up with some beautiful theory (ie guess) that experiment was against at the time. He decided to wait rather than abandon it. By his dictum he should have scrapped it - but it was just so beautiful. He was right - later experiments proved it.
It really is a strange thing. As one person expressed it, and even wrote a book with the title, there is fire in the equations. Trying to get to the bottom of it has led to some rather interesting views such as those of Penrose.
Me - I am with Gell-Mann:
Thanks
Bill
None of this is relevant. You guys have galloped off on some by-way.stevendaryl said:Yeah, there have been lots of examples where looking for a compelling theory galloped way ahead of experiment, and the experiments confirmed the beautiful theory was right. Some examples:
Of course, in recent years, there have been quite a few counter-examples, where the pursuit of an intellectually-pleasing theory turned out not to have any empirical support. I'm thinking the various GUT theories, supersymmetry, string theory.
- I think it's true that Maxwell introduced the "displacement current" because it fixed flaws in the mathematical appearance of his equations, rather than because there was any evidence for it.
- General relativity was really driven by Einstein's desire for a theory that elegantly incorporated gravity and Special Relativity, not because of evidence. The evidence came soon afterwards.
- Antiparticles and electron spin were predicted by Dirac's equation, which was motivated by an attempt to reconcile quantum mechanics with relativity (spin had already been discovered, but it comes naturally out of the Dirac equation).
Mentz114 said:None of this is relevant. You guys have galloped off on some by-way.
It is preposterous to say that symmetries and conserved charges and currents are irrelevant in Physics
None of those things--symmetry, conservation, transformations, etc.---is fundamental to the project of physics, which is about describing the world that we live in in a way that is precise enough (mathematically) to make predictions capable of falsification.
vanhees71 said:The averaging is over a large number (of order ##10^24##) of microscopic observables making up a macroscopic one.
In probability theory, the law of large numbers (LLN) is a theorem that describes the result of performing the same experiment a large number of times.
I wanted to know why you keep asking 'why can macroscopic objects not form superpositions ?'. You say that the 'rules of quantum mecanics demand it'.stevendaryl said:Well, your comments about symmetry were pretty far off-topic to start with, so it's a little strange for you to complain about relevance.
:
Mentz114 said:I wanted to know why you keep asking 'why can macroscopic objects not form superpositions ?'. You say that the 'rules of quantum mecanics demand it'.
Which rule says that ? How was that rule derived ?
bhobba said:It's exactly what Feynman said - nothing more - nothing less:
[..]
Me - I am with Gell-Mann:
Thanks
Bill
Our job as physicists is to see things simply, to understand a great many
complicated phenomena in a unified way, in terms of a few simple principles.
stevendaryl said:I think it's good form not use to quote symbols unless you're quoting. It's not fair to ask me to defend a statement that you just made up (such as "symmetries and conserved charges and currents are irrelevant in Physics").
Anyway, according to quantum mechanics, states obey the principle of superposition: If [itex]|A\rangle[/itex] is a state, and [itex]|B\rangle[/itex] is a state, then [itex]\alpha |A\rangle + \beta |B \rangle[/itex] is a state. Are you asking where that rule is stated? It's part of the definition of a Hilbert space.
Mentz114 said:If we're down to quoting authority - Steven Weinberg said
Ok, then why do you think classical physics works so well for macroscopic matter? The ensembles you cite are Gibbs ensembles, but the law of large number says that we measure almost with certainty a definite value for a macroscopic variable given the very small relative standard deviation of this variable of order ##\mathcal{O}1/\sqrt{N}##. So you can within this relatively negligible uncertainty predict the value for this macroscopic variable. That's how, in my understanding, the apparent deterministic nature of classical physics is principally explained within the statistical interpretation.stevendaryl said:But the law of large numbers is not just about any situation involving large numbers. It's specifically (from Wikipedia):
If we use a macroscopic device to measure, say, the spin of an electron, the [itex]10^{24}[/itex] is not the number of times we perform the experiment. So the law of large numbers is not obviously relevant.
vanhees71 said:Ok, then why do you think classical physics works so well for macroscopic matter?
Why do you think it should be possible?stevendaryl said:It should be possible, if measuring devices were treated no differently than microscopic systems, to restate the theory without mentioning measurements or macroscopic systems.
zonde said:Why do you think it should be possible?
Measuring devices are just bigger more complicated "particles".
You apply Born rule to measurements only. You do not apply Born rule to other interactions. At least this is my understanding.stevendaryl said:That's my point. If measuring devices are just complicated systems, and measurements are just complicated interactions, then the Born rule shouldn't treat measurements differently than any other interactions. But it does: The Born rule says "If you measure a quantity, you get an eigenvalue of the corresponding operator, with such-and-such probability."
Demystifier said:As long as ensemble interpretation refuses to talk about single measurements, it cannot say anything about the measurement problem.