Measurement problem in the Ensemble interpretation

In summary: The moon is in a particular momentum eigenstate, but the ensemble interpretation does not say why it doesn't show interference. In summary, the ensemble interpretation of QM does not address the measurement problem as it only applies to ensembles of similarly prepared systems and does not consider single measurements. It may seem to prevent the need for wave-function collapse, but it does not explain the outcomes of single measurements or the quantum to classical transition. The inability to address the measurement problem is a problem in itself. Additionally, the ensemble interpretation weakens the explanatory power of physics in explaining classical phenomena.
  • #106
RockyMarciano said:
how do you maintain this stability without conservation laws in a dynamical context?
The meter can exchange energy with the environment (e.g. it can absorb heat), so energy of the meter is not conserved. Yet, the meter as a solid object is stable. If the meter was made from liquid it would not be stable (and not useful as a meter) even when it's energy is constant. This demonstrates that stability and energy conservation are not directly related to each other.

More formally, consider a particle in a potential of the form
$$V(x,t)=\frac{kx^2}{2}+U(t)$$
where ##U(t)## is a positive non-constant function of time ##t##. Clearly this potential does not conserve energy. Yet, the particle position ##x=0## is stable, provided that ##k## is positive. If ##k## were negative the position ##x=0## would not be stable, even if ##U(t)## were zero. That's another demonstration that stability and energy conservation are not related.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #107
vanhees71 said:
I still don't get, what should be a problem with that. To the contrary thanks to Q(F)T we have a theory to describe such decays very well.

If there's a conserved charge, at least you know that it will be there forever in the one or the other form. To be sure that a once prepared particle is always there, of course it must be stable, because if there is only the tiniest probability for its decay, then you can never be sure that it is still there after some time. That's why it's called unstable.
Let me try to explain the problem once again. The conserved quantities (charge, energy, ...) do not change. But the role of dynamics is to describe the change. There are two types of change in QFT:
1) Changes of probabilities between detections. Those are described by local deterministic laws.
2) Clicks of detectors. Those are described by non-deterministic laws.

The 2) clearly does not reflect all the properties of 1), because 1) is deterministic and 2) is not. So, given that 2) is so fundamentally different from 1), what makes you think that 2) must be local?
 
  • #108
Now it's totally confusing. All that QT gives me is, given the preparation of the state initially, the probabilities for finding a certain value for any observable possible for the system. The click of a detector is such a measurement (e.g., for the presence of a particle in the detector). Of course, I don't know more than the probability for it to click. The click is due to interactions of the particle with the particles in the detector, governed by the same laws, so it's local.
 
  • #109
vanhees71 said:
The click is due to interactions of the particle with the particles in the detector, governed by the same laws, so it's local.
If it's due to the same laws, how can it be one of them are deterministic and other non-deterministic?

Or do you deny that unitary evolution of probability between measurements is deterministic?

Or do you claim that even between measurements something changes in a non-deterministic way? If so, what is it?
 
  • #110
I don't understand what you mean by deterministic then. The state implies only probabilities. So there's no deterministic content in it (except for the case of a precisely determined value of an observable). The (ideal) detector clicks with the probability given by the state according to Born's rule.
 
  • #111
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand what you mean by deterministic then. The state implies only probabilities. So there's no deterministic content in it (except for the case of a precisely determined value of an observable). The (ideal) detector clicks with the probability given by the state according to Born's rule.
By unitary evolution, if you know probability ##P(t)## for some ##t##, then you can calculate the probability ##P(t+\Delta t)##. That's deterministic evolution of probability. Between the clicks, probability evolves deterministically. At the moment of click, it is not so obvious whether it does or not.

Nevertheless, try to answer my last question in the post above:
Do you claim that even between measurements something changes in a non-deterministic way? If so, what is it?
 
Last edited:
  • #112
Of course between the clicks you have unitary time evolution. It's misleading to call it "deterministic", but I know what you mean. I don't know what you mean with the question whether the click is deterministic of not. It's the measurement, and about the measurement I only know probabilities. That's the whole point of saying QT is a probabilistic description, and what's probabilistic is not determined (except that the probability for the outcome of the measured observable is 100%).
 
  • #113
vanhees71 said:
Of course between the clicks you have unitary time evolution.
And how about the clicks themselves? Are they unitary too?

vanhees71 said:
It's the measurement, and about the measurement I only know probabilities.
And how about non-measurements? Can you say anything about probabilities of non-measured quantities?
 
  • #114
What do you mean by the "clicks are unitary" or "clicks are not unitary"?

As a physicist I don't need to talk about non-measured quantities since if I don't measure them, what should I be able to say about them?
 
  • #115
vanhees71 said:
What do you mean by the "clicks are unitary" or "clicks are not unitary"?
You said: "Of course between the clicks you have unitary time evolution."
In the same sense you meant that, I ask you: Do I also have unitary time evolution at the time of clicks?

vanhees71 said:
As a physicist I don't need to talk about non-measured quantities since if I don't measure them, what should I be able to say about them?
If so, then why do you keep saying that there is conserved charge in the absence of measurement? Why don't you say that you don't need to talk about conserved charge in the absence of measurement? It looks as if you use double standards.
 
  • #116
Demystifier said:
the meter as a solid object is stable.
Are you referring only to classical theory? Because this doesn't seem to be a valid assertion in the quantum realm, at least if we go by its theoretical principles. A solid meter is most likely made up of atoms joined by chemical bonds that act as springs with a ground state energy that fluctuates, the corresponding uncertainty in the length of the spring makes the separation between atoms at each step not well defined so that they shouldn't add up to a fixed and stable expected distance between marks on the meter and therefore it can't justify a robust measure remaining stable independently of how and when it is used as a measuring tool.

Of course in practice these shortcomings are overcome by obtaining a measurement that gives a defined distance that allows to introduce an idealized meter and the atomic fluctuations only produce a minor blurring for the position of each atom(for instance in x-ray scattering).
This demonstrates that stability and energy conservation are not directly related to each other.
You would have to show from first principles how the meter is stable taking into account the ground state energy fluctuations.
More formally, consider a particle in a potential of the form
$$V(x,t)=\frac{kx^2}{2}+U(t)$$
where ##U(t)## is a positive non-constant function of time ##t##. Clearly this potential does not conserve energy. Yet, the particle position ##x=0## is stable, provided that ##k## is positive. If ##k## were negative the position ##x=0## would not be stable, even if ##U(t)## were zero. That's another demonstration that stability and energy conservation are not related.
See above.
 
  • #117
Demystifier said:
You said: "Of course between the clicks you have unitary time evolution."
In the same sense you meant that, I ask you: Do I also have unitary time evolution at the time of clicks?If so, then why do you keep saying that there is conserved charge in the absence of measurement? Why don't you say that you don't need to talk about conserved charge in the absence of measurement? It looks as if you use double standards.
Sure, but you cannot evaluate it in practice since the detector is a macroscopic device. All you are interested in is a macroscopic very coarse-grained obsevable (in this case simply "click" or "no click").

The argument with conserved charge was to the question, why a particle is with certainty there. As I argued that's of course the case only for stable particles, and that usually conservation laws forbid its decay. If the particle is unstable, of course it decays with some probability and you cannot with certainty say whether it's still there but only give the probability of its survival. I don't know, why all of this is a "measurement problem". If you just stick to the minimal interpretation, there's never a contradiction. QT seems to be a pretty logically consistent probabilistic description of nature. It's also very successful, i.e., it's tested very well against observations, and the loopholes concerning the possibility of some local deterministic description are more and more closed too. So if you want to get back to a deterministic theory, you'd have to invent something non-local, and that seems to be very difficult, because so far nobody has come up with a convincing model. Maybe Bohmian mechanics is the most convincing, but on the other hand there seem to be predictions of "trajectories" that cannot be verified by experiment.
 
  • #118
vanhees71 said:
So if you want to get back to a deterministic theory, you'd have to invent something non-local
My main objection concerns the claim above. If by "deterministic" you mean the opposite of probabilistic, then, I claim, even without determinism you need something non-local. That's what I am repeatedly trying to explain to you in various ways, and that's what even Ballentine in his book explains in his own way. But somehow you fail to grasp any argument in that direction, because you always and up with an argument of the form: "The QFT dynamics is local" (which is true) "and hence we don't need anything non-local" (which is at least doubtful).
 
  • #119
This I don't understand. Classical electrodynamics (with a classical continuum description for the charged matter) is a local deterministic theory par excellance. Why, in your opnion, do I need to get non-local even in the non-quantum context?

The other argument is related to standard relativistic QFT, which is indeed local and probabilistic. So far we don't need anything non-local, because QFT (even the Standard Model) is very successful in describing all observed facts.

Here we discuss something else, namely possible theories going beyond standard Q(F)T, maybe deterministic ones. In the latter case, imho it's pretty clear that we'd need a non-local formulation if you want to have a deterministic theory that can describe what's described by entanglement in QFT.
 
  • #120
vanhees71 said:
Why, in your opnion, do I need to get non-local even in the non-quantum context?
I didn't say that we need it in non-quantum context. Why do you think I did?

vanhees71 said:
So far we don't need anything non-local, because QFT...
And I disagree. I claim that even QFT has something implicit non-local in it. But I cannot explain it to you without repeating my arguments which you failed to grasp.
 
  • #121
Demystifier said:
. But I cannot explain it to you without repeating my arguments which you failed to grasp.

Lurking, with a suggestion: Since you have mentioned Ballentine explaining this "in his own way," perhaps you could give this cite with enough detail to be looked up? That might provide a way around the explanatory deadlock.
 
  • #122
UsableThought said:
Lurking, with a suggestion: Since you have mentioned Ballentine explaining this "in his own way," perhaps you could give this cite with enough detail to be looked up? That might provide a way around the explanatory deadlock.
Well, I already did it for @vanhees71 in an older thread.
Would studying MWI be a waste of time?
 
  • #123
I have this weird feeling that although QFT is just QM applied to classical field theories, practically we do different things in QFT and QM. Its true that calculating the probability amplitudes of a particular kind of scattering using perturbation theory is something that can be done in both QFT and QM, but when we talk about foundational problems in QM, its not scattering experiments that we're thinking about. In such discussions we tend to think about problems that allow us to think about the state of the system as a whole while at the same time provide us with a clear way to recognize the system as being consisted of subsystems that can be objectively identified. I just have this feeling that there is not much of this nature in the problems that we usually deal with in QFT. Specially because we're always dealing with this perturbation series and Feynman diagrams that somehow are just an incomplete and small part of the solution(Yeah, numerically they may be good approximations, but conceptually they're in no way close to a clear picture of what's going on).
It may stem from my lack of knowledge, but it seems to me that its infinitely harder to talk about foundational problems of QM in the context of QFT. So it just doesn't make sense to me that someone gives the same explanations to dismiss those foundational problems in both theories. It seems to me this is what @vanhees71 is doing. I'm just getting more and more convinced that he just dismisses these problems because he's in the group of physicists who are happy with the fact that they can apply QM to their problems and get accurate enough results(Not that there is anything wrong with this approach).
Sorry if I'm just rambling but I kind of think I have something in my mind but I'm not so sure what
 
  • #124
I think that's the usual confusion between "local interactions" and "long-ranged correlations". The latter are included in rel. QFT in terms of entanglement which can correlate far-distant parts of a quantum system. With "local" I always refer to the properties that the QFT should be microcausal and the Lagrangian a polynomial in the fields and its derivatives at one space-time point (as implemented in the Standard Model).
 
  • #125
ShayanJ said:
I have this weird feeling that although QFT is just QM applied to classical field theories, practically we do different things in QFT and QM. Its true that calculating the probability amplitudes of a particular kind of scattering using perturbation theory is something that can be done in both QFT and QM, but when we talk about foundational problems in QM, its not scattering experiments that we're thinking about. In such discussions we tend to think about problems that allow us to think about the state of the system as a whole while at the same time provide us with a clear way to recognize the system as being consisted of subsystems that can be objectively identified. I just have this feeling that there is not much of this nature in the problems that we usually deal with in QFT. Specially because we're always dealing with this perturbation series and Feynman diagrams that somehow are just an incomplete and small part of the solution(Yeah, numerically they may be good approximations, but conceptually they're in no way close to a clear picture of what's going on).
It may stem from my lack of knowledge, but it seems to me that its infinitely harder to talk about foundational problems of QM in the context of QFT. So it just doesn't make sense to me that someone gives the same explanations to dismiss those foundational problems in both theories. It seems to me this is what @vanhees71 is doing. I'm just getting more and more convinced that he just dismisses these problems because he's in the group of physicists who are happy with the fact that they can apply QM to their problems and get accurate enough results(Not that there is anything wrong with this approach).
Sorry if I'm just rambling but I kind of think I have something in my mind but I'm not so sure what
Well, yes, that's exactly my point of view. I don't see the need for a deterministic theory or any other theory as long as there's no empirical evidence against the theories we have now. I'm very pragmatic in seeing no fundamental problems like "measurement problems", as long as we can use QFT to get all observed facts described by it. A measurement is defined by a real-world measurement apparatus, and there's nothing hinting that one needs more than statistical quantum physics to understand the macroscopic behavior of these measurement apparati in terms of the underlying microphysics. The socalled measurement problem is some quibble of philosophers who have not learned to abandon the classical thinking of what's often called "common sense", but it's just experience of macroscopic matter in everyday life, and as far as the fundamental theories are concerned their classical behavior is well compatible with the underlying quantum dynamics thanks to the coarse-grained nature of macroscopic observables.

Of course, there's the great enigma about a consistent quantization of gravity, and maybe this problem needs an extension of our "foundational toolbox".
 
  • #126
vanhees71 said:
I'm very pragmatic in seeing no fundamental problems like "measurement problems", as long as we can use QFT to get all observed facts described by it.
I find this thread interesting, so I hope that I understand everyone's position correctly. Yours seems pretty straightforward except:
vanhees71 said:
A measurement is defined by a real-world measurement apparatus,
The singular here kind of undermine your previous statement in my view. Because QFT cannot event give any hint about an observed fact. Only a series of facts (whose count is quite fuzzy) will do, already turning the experiment into a "macro" experiment, whatever the apparatus is made of.

vanhees71 said:
and there's nothing hinting that one needs more than statistical quantum physics to understand the macroscopic behavior of these measurement apparati in terms of the underlying microphysics.
But isn't there the obvious hint of entanglement ? Doesn't it prove that there are some single fact (like correlation at some angle) that can be absolutely known/predicted non-statistically ?

Isn't the point of Demystifier to show that there are other hints, like the two spacially separated ends of a stern gerlach experiment kind of certainly knows how to always individually "click" in opposite way (without entanglement needed) ?
 
  • Like
Likes entropy1
  • #127
From many discussions of interpretative problems with @vanhees71 , I would say that his interpretation is some mixture of shut-up-and-calculate interpretation, minimal statistical ensemble interpretation, and instrumental interpretation. Each of these interpretations by itself is legitimate and logically consistent. But neither interpretation is perfect, so people naturally try to mix different interpretations hoping that this will somehow remedy or alleviate deficiencies of individual interpretations. Unfortunately, mixing often makes more harm than good. By mixing different interpretations one easily falls into logical and conceptual inconsistencies, and some people (like me) have not much tolerance for such inconsistencies. Other people don't care much about such inconsistencies (after all, that's mere philosophy), as long as it does not affect their computations of actually measurable quantities.

People who care about something should not talk about it with people who don't care. I should not discuss quantum interpretations with @vanhees71 , but somehow I always fall in the same trap. I always think like this: (1) he is smart and (2) he likes to talk about interpretations, so therefore (3) it must be fruitful to discuss interpretations with him. But that's wrong, (3) does not follow from (1) and (2).
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and UsableThought
  • #128
Demystifier said:
People who care about something should not talk about it with people who don't care.

Absolutely true - hard-won, late-life wisdom, in my case. And also true that most of us who care violate this rule and then regret it, over and over. The illusion of potential fruitfulness that you mention as point #3 persists.

Oddly enough a similar though not identical dilemma applies to real-world negotiations, where two persons (friends or colleagues or partners or spouses or what have you) must divide responsibilities, and as it happens one person cares much more about a particular responsibility than the other. Take for example a married couple, A and B: A cares very much about keeping a clean kitchen, but B is a slob and doesn't care at all. A attempts to put moral pressure on B to agree to do more cleaning up. B nominally agrees so as to keep the peace; but because B really does not care at all, B still doesn't do enough cleaning to satisfy A. Unfortunately, because A really cannot tolerate a dirty kitchen, he/she will then pick up the slack, resenting it every time but powerless to do anything else.

The only way this situation can change is if A possesses superior leverage of another sort and is willing to bring it to bear, even at the risk of alienating B; this superior leverage is called a BATNA, or "best alternative to a negotiated agreement." I learned about BATNAs many decades ago from a book written by a college friend of mine: Kidding Ourselves: Breadwinning, Babies, And Bargaining Power, by Rhona Mahoney. You can read more about BATNAs in a Wikipedia article, link here. A BATNA can be summed up as a feasible option to remaining in a relationship. Whoever has the best BATNA in theory has more leverage - but only if they are ruthless enough to apply it and risk alienating the other person.

But here on PF of course no one has a BATNA. So the only cure for caring too much is to sigh when this is recognized and once again leave off.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #129
Demystifier said:
People who care about something should not talk about it with people who don't care.
Good motto. So just to be sure, do you care about your statement "the meter as a solid object is stable" in quantum physics as it pertains to the measurement problem?
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #130
Yes, indeed. I also always fall into the same trap, thinking it might help to keep the discussion away from philosophy and stay closer to physics ;-).
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #131
Demystifier said:
People who care about something should not talk about it with people who don't care.
While both parties are willing to discuss, I see no harm in that. planting seed don't guarantee a result. But on the long run, even if fruitless, it may help to guess is the seed is wrong, or the soil, or the weather. As a spectator I found all posts quite interesting ! I am sure I am not the only one...

To get back on physics, I have a hard time understanding when interpretations comes into play here. Maybe if the Q in QFT or QM stands for Quanta (plural) instead of Quantum (singular) then we won't have any grey area to refine.

Have you some link on "instrumental interpretation", so I can see if it en-light the "problem" that all experiments seem to deal with single event while the theory deals with the statistics about a series of those experiments ?
 
  • #132
RockyMarciano said:
Good motto. So just to be sure, do you care about your statement "the meter as a solid object is stable" in quantum physics as it pertains to the measurement problem?
No, I don't care much about that because it looks kind of trivial to me (but I could be wrong). Sorry! :biggrin:
 
  • #133
Hm, as a pragmatist I'd say that the stability of matter, among them "the meter as a solid object" (I guess you are referring to the original metre prototype) is among the prime arguments for the validity of QT, given the atomistic structure of matter. There's no known way to explain this stability within classical physics. Contrary to the socalled "measurement problem", which is a pseudoproblem since QT's predictions are regularly verified in the lab with astonishing accuracy, the problem of stability of matter is a highly non-trivial one solved by QT!
 
  • #134
vanhees71 said:
Hm, as a pragmatist I'd say that the stability of matter, among them "the meter as a solid object" (I guess you are referring to the original metre prototype) is among the prime arguments for the validity of QT, given the atomistic structure of matter. There's no known way to explain this stability within classical physics. Contrary to the socalled "measurement problem", which is a pseudoproblem since QT's predictions are regularly verified in the lab with astonishing accuracy, the problem of stability of matter is a highly non-trivial one solved by QT!
How does QT solve it? I'm not sure what you are referring to by this? Would you take a look to my post #116 and tell me how this is addressed from first principles by QT?
EDIT: I think you are confusing my question with the classical problem of stability of matter(why electrons don't fall in the nuclei and similar stuff), my post was not about that but rather about the reliability of a solid rod as a mesuring tool according to quantum mechanics.
 
Last edited:
  • #135
vanhees71 said:
... Contrary to the socalled "measurement problem", which is a pseudoproblem since QT's predictions are regularly verified in the lab with astonishing accuracy...

I agree with a great deal of what you are saying. However, when reading “Why Decoherence has not Solved the Measurement Problem: A Response to P.W. Anderson” by Stephen L. Adler, I am not thinking that the "measurement problem” is a “pseudoproblem”.
 
  • #136
Demystifier said:
No, I don't care much about that because it looks kind of trivial to me (but I could be wrong). Sorry! :biggrin:
Fair enough. However more often than we think the key to a problem lies in reconsidering what seems trivial.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #137
Lord Jestocost said:
I agree with a great deal of what you are saying. However, when reading “Why Decoherence has not Solved the Measurement Problem: A Response to P.W. Anderson” by Stephen L. Adler, I am not thinking that the "measurement problem” is a “pseudoproblem”.
The difference between problems and pseudo-problems is subjective. Any problem can be turned into a pseudo-problem by a change of perspective. Anyone is welcome to challenge me by a "serious" problem that I will try to turn into a pseudo-problem by a change of perspective, just to prove my point.
 
  • #138
RockyMarciano said:
Fair enough. However more often than we think the key to a problem lies in reconsidering what seems trivial.
That's certainly true. But then again, no single individual can reconsider all problems that seem trivial, so one has to be picky.
 
  • Like
Likes Boing3000 and RockyMarciano
  • #139
Demystifier said:
That's certainly true. But then again, no single individual can reconsider all problems that seem trivial, so one has to be picky.
Maybe you wouldn't mind giving the trivial answer to the objections to a robust solid meter in QM given in #116, then?
 
  • #140
@Demystifier , I have the feeling that, at least in part if not fully, the problem you have is because of overuse of the term "non-local". Have you tried to explain it by giving the exact same argument but using a different word and never mentioning "non-local"?
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier

Similar threads

Replies
84
Views
4K
Replies
309
Views
12K
Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
91
Views
6K
Replies
14
Views
2K
Replies
109
Views
5K
Replies
90
Views
8K
Back
Top