- #246
- 14,342
- 6,824
What orientation of the Stern-Gerlach apparatus will the experimentalist freely choose in the next experimental run.A. Neumaier said:on many interesting questions that can be checked experimentally? What would be an example?
What orientation of the Stern-Gerlach apparatus will the experimentalist freely choose in the next experimental run.A. Neumaier said:on many interesting questions that can be checked experimentally? What would be an example?
vanhees71 said:Sure, what I meant is that there is not the slightest evidence for a failure of the purely quantum theoretical description.
stevendaryl said:But to me, the fact that the two halves of a quantum experiment--the system being measured, and the system doing the measuring--have such completely different properties according to the quantum formalism suggests to me that the burden of proof should be on the other side. Prove that hamiltonian dynamics is sufficient to account for all phenomena, including measurement processes.
Many-worlds is an attempt to do that. A. Neumaier claims that it can be done without many-worlds (although I don't understand his argument). But it seems to me that some kind of derivation of measurement from hamiltonian dynamics is needed before you can say that hamiltonian dynamics applies to everything.
The problem for me is that the standard way that quantum mechanics is done postulates properties for measurement devices and measurement interactions which it does not postulate for single particles, or any combination of particles. If you have a single electron that is in the spin state [itex]\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (|U\rangle + |D\rangle[/itex], then it doesn't make any sense to say that it is 50% likely to be spin-up and 50% likely to be spin-down. It is in the definite state "spin-up in the x-direction". If you have an interaction between two electrons, it doesn't make any sense to say that one electron has a 50% chance of observing the other to be spin-up. With a small number of particles, probability doesn't come into play at all. Definite values for dynamic variables doesn't come into play at all. But if you scale up one of the interacting systems to be a measurement device designed to measure spin, then it becomes unproblematic to say that the measurement device interacting with the electron has a 50% chance of going into the "observed spin-up" state, and 50% chance of going into the "observed spin-down" state. How did this probabilistic description arise from microscopic interactions that are non-probabilistic?
Which feature of QT contradicts the fact that the moon is there when one is not looking? To the contrary the conservation laws ensuring that the moon is not spontaneously puffing out of existence are also at the very beginning of Q(F)T model building ;-).atyy said:If one believes the moon is there when one is not looking, then one should believe the quantum description is incomplete (or that many-worlds is correct).
Yes, I think to say that any of the interpretations of QT are saying that the Moon isn't there when we are not looking at it misses the point-- that's Einstein's straw man. Of course the Moon is there when we are not looking at it, the problem is, it is only our ability to look at it that allows us to say it is there when we aren't.vanhees71 said:Which feature of QT contradicts the fact that the moon is there when one is not looking? To the contrary the conservation laws ensuring that the moon is not spontaneously puffing out of existence are also at the very beginning of Q(F)T model building ;-).
vanhees71 said:Which feature of QT contradicts the fact that the moon is there when one is not looking? To the contrary the conservation laws ensuring that the moon is not spontaneously puffing out of existence are also at the very beginning of Q(F)T model building ;-).
atyy said:If the moon is always there, then the moon has a trajectory, so particles have trajectories.
vanhees71 said:Yes, FAPP the moon has a trajectory, but just in principle, how implies the statement that "the moon is there when one is not looking" that "the moon has a trajectory"? If I say there is a container with walls at a certain temperature, it includes the black-body radiation of this temperature (no matter whether I look at it or not), it also hasn't a trajectory.
I mean I can measure its spectrum (in principle).atyy said:You mean the black body radiation has classical field values.
vanhees71 said:I mean I can measure its spectrum (in principle).
Again, you are mixing individual properties and ensemble properties. The property of moon being or not being there is an individual property, on which standard Q(F)T does not say much. The conservation law of Q(F)T is an ensemble property.vanhees71 said:Which feature of QT contradicts the fact that the moon is there when one is not looking? To the contrary the conservation laws ensuring that the moon is not spontaneously puffing out of existence are also at the very beginning of Q(F)T model building ;-).
This is a nonsense question, because I cannot check whether it exists without looking at it ;-).atyy said:But does its spectrum exist when you are not measuring it?
If I have prepared a photon with some (pretty well defined) momentum, then it's there due to this preparation procedure and it has a (pretty well defined) momentum, no matter whether I detect it or not. Maybe I'm again to naive to understand (and I've never understood this argument), why this is a problem at all.Demystifier said:Again, you are mixing individual properties and ensemble properties. The property of moon being or not being there is an individual property, on which standard Q(F)T does not say much. The conservation law of Q(F)T is an ensemble property.
To sharpen the problem, consider the following questions:
Is the photon momentum there when nobody looks?
If yes, isn't that an assumption of hidden-variables?
If no, isn't that a violation of momentum conservation?
If the question has no answer within Q(F)T, then is there an answer to the same question when photon is replaced by Moon?
The question, of course, refers to the case in which you have prepared the photon in a state with not pretty well defined momentum.vanhees71 said:If I have prepared a photon with some (pretty well defined) momentum, then it's there due to this preparation procedure and it has a (pretty well defined) momentum, no matter whether I detect it or not. Maybe I'm again to naive to understand (and I've never understood this argument), why this is a problem at all.
vanhees71 said:This is a nonsense question, because I cannot check whether it exists without looking at it ;-).
But then it is an equal nonsense to claim that Moon exists without looking at it.vanhees71 said:This is a nonsense question, because I cannot check whether it exists without looking at it ;-).
If you were saying that it is nonsense to say that the Moon is there when nobody looks, then why did you use the conservation law to argue that it is there when nobody looks?vanhees71 said:Yes, that's what I was saying the whole time.
No I said that the claim the moon is not there is nonsense to begin with. It has been observed in the past. Then there are pretty well established conservation laws telling you that it won't puff out of existence only because nobody is looking at her.Demystifier said:If you were saying that it is nonsense to say that the Moon is there when nobody looks, then why did you use the conservation law to argue that it is there when nobody looks?
I have no further comments on this, because you explained your position consistently in #267.vanhees71 said:Then, of course, it doesn't have a (pretty well defined) momentum. So what?
vanhees71 said:No I said that the claim the moon is not there is nonsense to begin with. It has been observed in the past. Then there are pretty well established conservation laws telling you that it won't puff out of existence only because nobody is looking at her.
Again, it's not necessary for the moon to have a trajectory only for "being there". Strictly speaking the moon has no trajectory since nothing has an exact trajectory, because this contradicts the position-momentum uncertainty relation. As a macroscopic object in the sense of the classical approximation, of course, its center of mass has a trajectory (not easy to calculate, as already made Kepler crazy ;-)).atyy said:So if the moon has a trajectory, there are hidden variables.
vanhees71 said:Again, it's not necessary for the moon to have a trajectory only for "being there". Strictly speaking the moon has no trajectory since nothing has an exact trajectory, because this contradicts the position-momentum uncertainty relation. As a macroscopic object in the sense of the classical approximation, of course, its center of mass has a trajectory (not easy to calculate, as already made Kepler crazy ;-)).
I don't believe in hidden variables, but of course, I cannot disprove their existence. Maybe after all nature is deterministic with non-local interactions, but we are not clever enough (yet?) to find an adequate theory of such a possibility and also no experiment to observe the hidden variables (yet?).
A hypothetic question: If you lived in time when Boltzmann had a theory that thermodynamics is a consequence of motion of atoms, while Mach argued against existence of atoms because there was no any direct experimental evidence for atoms, on whose side would you be at that time (given the evidence at that time)?vanhees71 said:I don't believe in hidden variables, but of course, I cannot disprove their existence.
vanhees71 said:But ##x(t)## doesn't exist in the classical sense, because it's uncertain anyway. Given you start with a pretty well located particle. Then it has a pretty unsharp momentum, and thus with time, also the position uncertainty grows. So there are only trajectories in a coarse-grained sense, i.e., not in the sense of accurate values ##x(t)## as in classical physics!
This is a statement without any logical support.atyy said:If one believes the moon is there when one is not looking, then one should believe the quantum description is incomplete
That's difficult to say. As a physicist probably I'd have taken the side of Mach, although if I'd have been be a bit more open minded and taking the vast evidence of "atomism" from chemistry at the time, maybe I'd have taken Boltzmann's side since his model at least didn't contradict any evidence (and it was appealing mathematically).Demystifier said:A hypothetic question: If you lived in time when Boltzmann had a theory that thermodynamics is a consequence of motion of atoms, while Mach argued against existence of atoms because there was no any direct experimental evidence for atoms, on whose side would you be at that time (given the evidence at that time)?
The moon need only to have a mean trajectory, given by the expectation of the center of mass of the position operators of its atoms. Its standard deviation is far below the radius of the moon and hence negligible.atyy said:If the moon is always there, then the moon has a trajectory, so particles have trajectories.
vanhees71 said:Given the state ##\hat{\rho}_{\sigma_x=1/2}=|\sigma_x=1/2 \rangle\langle \sigma_x=1/2 |## with ##|\sigma_x=1/2 \rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (|\sigma_z=1/2 \rangle+|\sigma_z=-1/2 \rangle)## means, according to minimally interpreted QT, with regard to a measurment of ##\sigma_z## not more and not less that you'll find with 50% probality up and with 50% probability down when measuring ##\sigma_z##. That's it.
vanhees71 said:If I have prepared a photon with some (pretty well defined) momentum, then it's there due to this preparation procedure and it has a (pretty well defined) momentum, no matter whether I detect it or not. Maybe I'm again to naive to understand (and I've never understood this argument), why this is a problem at all.