Possibilities of Time-Independent Entangled Photons

  • A
  • Thread starter DrChinese
  • Start date
In summary, "Possibilities of Time-Independent Entangled Photons" explores the generation and application of entangled photons that do not depend on time-varying processes. The study highlights their potential for enhancing quantum communication, improving secure information transfer, and enabling advanced quantum computing techniques. It discusses methods for creating such photons, their unique properties, and the implications for future quantum technologies, emphasizing the importance of time-independent entanglement in practical applications.
  • #36
Morbert said:
Fig 2 from @DrChinese 's paper
@DrChinese has referenced quite a few papers. Which one?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #38
Morbert said:
Ok. In that paper the state that is produced is, as I described before, a product state of two entangled photon pairs. (In equation 3 of the paper the state before the projection operation on photons 2 & 3 is given, but the following text makes it clear that after the projection operation, you simply have one of the four Bell states given in equation 3, and each of those is as I described.)

But in the other paper, the one you referenced, the state after the projection operation on the photons at time ##\tau## (which correspond to photons 2 & 3) is a four-photon entangled state (the GHZ state). And the process that paper describes, as I said before, is set up to produce a single entangled state containing any even number of photons (just do the BBO operation more times).

I don't see any explanation in either paper of how to produce a product state of two separate entangled photon pairs using the given setup.
 
  • #39
A. Neumaier said:
I. So we have an entangled 4-photon state in the standard meaning, a tetraphoton, but not an entangled 2-photon state, no biphoton. The paper just shows that certain tetraphotons measured at different times produce the same correlations as a biphoton in a Bell state, and tries to sell it as ''temporal entanglement''.

II. But they don't substantiate this claim, and indeed, the claim is meaningless.

I. Sorry, perhaps either I (most likely) or the authors of the paper were not clear. There is an N=4 photon state, but there is no tetraphoton as you mention. The 4 photon state(s) in the generalized entanglement swapping regime starts as a Product state of 2 biphotons*, and end also as a Product state of 2 biphotons (although your method of photon counting produces a different result in some specific cases):

a. Initial Product state: |ψ-12> |ψ-34>
b. Execute Swap: Photons 2 & 3 are allowed to overlap such that their identities become indistinguishable. You could also say that biphotons (1 & 2) and (3 & 4) are allowed to overlap.
c. Final Product state: |φ+/-14> |φ+/-23>II. The paper follows standard QM predictive methods, using quantum theory (that measurement order in entanglement swaps is irrelevant to the observed statistics) that was published at least 25 years ago. Their specific hypothesis was that measuring Photon 1 before the swap (BSM) would lead to predicted violations of Bell-type inequalities just the same as if they had measured Photon 1 after the swap. That hypothesis was substantiated, yet another confirmation of quantum mechanics - and to nobody's surprise.

It was published in Physical Review Letters 110, 210403; 22 May 2013. Obviously it passed peer review. There have been no published works that contradict or otherwise criticize their work (that I am aware of). Perhaps you are aware of published work that contradicts this result. So I question your evaluation of their results as "meaningless". I would say this is an important paper that deserves proper respect and consideration, even if you disagree with elements of it - which you are certainly free to do. I recognize your expertise in the math around the Schrödinger equation from your extensive published works. But I really think you should take a second look here.



To summarize the line of research on the nature of measurements in entanglement swapping, which was the reason I posted in this thread to begin with:

At this time, there has been experimental verification (references below from 2002 to 2012) of the following:
  1. Basic Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Zeilinger et al, etc.
  2. Entanglement Swap with fully independent sources with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Zeilinger et al, etc.
  3. Remote (photons 1 & 4 outside each others' light cone) Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Gisin et al, etc.
  4. Delayed Choice Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed subsequent to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Ma et al, etc.
  5. Temporal Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of photon 4 but subsequent to observation of photon 4. See Eisenberg et al.
  6. Failure of Temporal Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed without indistinguishability** of photons 2 & 3, prior to observation of photon 4 but subsequent to observation of photon 4. See Eisenberg et al.
Hopefully, the pattern is clear: the same results are obtained, regardless of measurement order. The only requirement that must be met is that the Bell State Measurement of photons (2 & 3) must result in indistinguishability between 2 & 3. When that is not accomplished, there is no swap and there is no Bell State consisting of 1 & 4. If your viewpoint (or interpretation or mental picture or whatever) does not accommodate the 6 experimental facts listed, you might want to review them to understand why not.

I am not aware of any aspects of relativistic QFT that would add to this discussion or lead to any predictions contrary to garden variety QM. But I would certainly be interested in viewpoints from anyone following this.*Each biphoton contains photons that are maximally entangled, but there is no entanglement (or correlation) whatsoever with the other biphoton.
** This outcome is predicted by theory.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost
  • #40
A. Neumaier said:
The paper just shows that certain tetraphotons measured at different times produce the same correlations as a biphoton in a Bell state, and tries to sell it as ''temporal entanglement''.

This. In a nutshell.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes DrChinese
  • #41
mattt said:
This. In a nutshell.
Sorry, no. See my post #91, which explains why not. Arnold misread (or misinterpreted) something amongst the many posts. It would be easy for anyone to do. :smile:

Entanglement swapping protocols don't use 4-photon GHZ entanglement (what was referred to as "tetraphotons" in some posts). Obviously, with 4-photon GHZ entanglement there is no entanglement to swap within its components, as they are all already entangled with each other.

Instead, the Entanglement Swapping regime uses a Product state of biphotons (entangled photon pairs). These Product states can be even be daisy-chained together: 2 pairs=2 biphotons, 3 pairs=3 biphotons, etc. And any of the related measurements can be performed in any order the experimenter is able to achieve.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost
  • #42
What I mean is that in the case where biphoton1,2 is created and photon1 is measured (and destroyed) before (for all possible reference frames) biphoton3,4 is created, there can be no biphoton1,4 Bell State (or any biphoton1,4 state).

I must conclude that you (and possibly the authors of that paper) are using these English words with a different meaning than the usual mathematical meaning.
 
  • #43
DrChinese said:
Entanglement swapping protocols don't use 4-photon GHZ entanglement
Yes, I agree. What I'm still not sure about is how the state they do use, which is, as you say, a product state of two biphotons (the entanglement swap just changes which photons are in each biphoton), is produced by the apparatus that is described. The paper that describes the theoretical background, at least in a little bit of detail, only talks about how the GHZ state is produced. The paper that you referenced that describes the entanglement swapping, and uses the two-biphoton states (with similar temporal markings to the 4-photon GHZ states in the other paper), does not describe how those two-biphoton states are produced by the apparatus, and it's not clear to me from the description in the first paper (the GHZ state paper) how pair-of-biphoton states could be produced. Possibly there are other papers (which would hopefully be somewhere in the references in those two papers) that go into more detail about the latter; but I haven't seen any yet.
 
  • #44
PeterDonis said:
Yes, I agree. What I'm still not sure about is how the state they do use, which is, as you say, a product state of two biphotons (the entanglement swap just changes which photons are in each biphoton), is produced by the apparatus that is described. The paper that describes the theoretical background, at least in a little bit of detail, only talks about how the GHZ state is produced. The paper that you referenced that describes the entanglement swapping, and uses the two-biphoton states (with similar temporal markings to the 4-photon GHZ states in the other paper), does not describe how those two-biphoton states are produced by the apparatus, and it's not clear to me from the description in the first paper (the GHZ state paper) how pair-of-biphoton states could be produced. Possibly there are other papers (which would hopefully be somewhere in the references in those two papers) that go into more detail about the latter; but I haven't seen any yet.
The 2 biphoton (2 photon entangled system, i.e. an entangled photon pair) Product state (N=2x2) used for the initial portion of the entanglement swapping can be produced through a number of interesting and innovative methods. Here are a few, including reference links:

a. Here they pass a laser pulse forward and backward (from a mirror) through a PDC crystal. Some pulses yield a biphoton in the forward direction or the backward direction, but usually not both. About 1 in 15 of those yield biphotons coming out both directions of the PDC crystal simultaneously. The biphoton pairs - 4 total photons labeled (0 & 1) and (2 & 3) - are in a Product State, as they are actually produced independently.
Zeilinger1.JPG


b. Here they synchronize a slave laser to a master laser.
Zeilinger2.JPG


c. Here they sync two source lasers to a common signal. Each laser pumps a PDC crystal to create a biphoton. The sources are 12+ km apart. Note that this setup allows the order of measurement to be selected at will, as well as the spatial separation. The authors so noted: "...the configuration of our experiment allows the space-like separation between any two measurements of those performed in the three nodes, and various of time-space relation can be achieved by combining both coiled optical fiber and deployed optical fiber."
Pan3.JPG


d. Here they use the same pump laser in line serially to fire 2 PDC crystals.
Ma4.JPG


e. Here they pump successive pulses into a single PDC crystal to create 2 biphotons, one of which is routed a little differently than the other.
x
Eisenberg5.JPG
Note: In all of these configurations, the creation of 2 entangled pairs suitable for the experiment occurs randomly, perhaps on the order of 10-100 per second. Only 4 fold coincidences are considered for data collection. Further, there is the requirement that the photon overlap in the Bell State Measurement (BSM) portion of the apparatus be narrow enough so that the outputs of the beam splitter are indistinguishable in all degrees of freedom. I.e. the source should not be able to be determined. Also, only 1 or 2 of the 4 possible Bell states can be determined using current optical technology. This does not affect the fidelity or validity of the results in any way.
 
Last edited:
  • #45
DrChinese said:
The 2 biphoton (2 photon entangled system, i.e. an entangled photon pair) Product state (N=2x2) used for the initial portion of the entanglement swapping can be produced through a number of interesting and innovative methods.
I'm not asking about how biphoton states are produced experimentally. I already know there are multiple ways of doing that.

I am asking about how products of two two-photon entangled Bell states are produced mathematically using a theory that, as far as I can tell, only explains how the apparatus described in both the entanglement swapping paper you referenced and the "temporal mode" paper that @Morbert referenced (which describes the theory, though not in very great detail) can produce 4-photon GHZ states.
 
  • #46
PeterDonis said:
1. I'm not asking about how biphoton states are produced experimentally. I already know there are multiple ways of doing that.

2I am asking about how products of two two-photon entangled Bell states are produced mathematically using a theory that, as far as I can tell, only explains how the apparatus described in both the entanglement swapping paper you referenced and the "temporal mode" paper that @Morbert referenced (which describes the theory, though not in very great detail) can produce 4-photon GHZ states.
1. Well, you said (so I answered): "The paper that you referenced that describes the entanglement swapping, and uses the two-biphoton states (with similar temporal markings to the 4-photon GHZ states in the other paper), does not describe how those two-biphoton states are produced by the apparatus..." So I provided 5 examples with references. Note that none of these produce 4-photon GHZ states. I think that you and several others like the theory presented in a reference @Morbert provided in post #83. But that is a different state than the 2 biphotons in a Product State - as I think you acknowledge.2. Here is what I believe is the mathematical representation you seek, which is presented verbatim in italics and in context without interruption from several papers:

a. From HERE, circa 2002 (provided to show that my primary reference is using well-established theory and experimental confirmation):

Initially, the system is composed of two independent entangled states and can be written in the following way:

|Ψ>total = |Ψ−>01 ⊗ |Ψ−>23

Including equation (1) in (2) and rearranging the resulting terms by expressing photon 1 and photon 2 in the basis of Bell states leads to:

|Ψ>Total = 1/2 [
|Ψ+>03 |Ψ+>12
-|Ψ−>03 |Ψ−>12
-|φ+>03 |φ+>12
+|φ−>03 |φ−>12 ].

Alice subjects photons 1 and 2 to a measurement in a Bell-state analyzer (BSA)
[also called BSM in other papers], and if she finds them in the state |Ψ−>12, then photons 0 and 3 measured by Bob, will be in the entangled state |Ψ−>03. If Alice observes any of the other Bell-states for photons 1 and 2, photons 0 and 3 will also be perfectly entangled correspondingly.b. From HERE (my primary reference, and note that the starting and ending points are exactly the same as the one above, although labeled differently):

In order to generate consecutive photon pairs at well defined times, a pulsed laser is used to pump a single PDC polarization entangled photon source [4]. It is a probabilistic source, and thus there is a probability that two pairs will be created, each pair from one of two consecutive pulses, separated by the laser period time τ. The four-photon state is

[|Ψ>total] = |Ψ−>0, 0ab ⊗ |Ψ−>τ, τab

where the subscripts are the spatial mode labels and the superscripts are the time labels of the photons. In order to project the second photon of the first pair and the first photon of the second pair onto a Bell state, the former is delayed by τ in a delay line. The same delay is also applied to the second photon of the second pair and the resulting state can be reordered and written as

|Ψ−>0, τab ⊗ |Ψ−>τ, 2τab = 1/2(
|Ψ+>0, 2τab |Ψ+>τ, τab
-|Ψ−>0, 2τab |Ψ−>τ, τab
-|φ+>0, 2τab |φ+>τ, τab
+|φ−>0, 2τab |φ−>τ, τab )

When the two photons of time τ (photons 2 and 3) are projected onto any Bell state, the first and last photons (1 and 4) collapse also into the same state and entanglement is swapped. The first and last photons, that did not share between them any correlations, become entangled.




Please note the nearly identical language in both of these experiments, which I would refer to as so common in experimental papers as to be unquestioned at this point. The point of difference - which is of course why the b. paper was published in PRL in the first place - is that time superscripts are added to the label to show that there is "Entanglement between photons that never coexisted" (the title of the paper).

If these unambiguous and well presented theoretical and experimental research developments, published in PRL and culminating in a Nobel for one of the authors, is not sufficient to convince readers: I'm just not sure what the point of this thread is. Here, we investigate some of the most detail elements of measurements in QFT (title of the thread) and change of state via entanglement swapping. When does measurement occur? Where does measurement occur? What causes change of state? When and where does that occur?
 
Last edited:
  • #47
DrChinese said:
I provided 5 examples with references. Note that none of these produce 4-photon GHZ states.
You provided 5 references that describe experiments. That's not what I'm asking for.

DrChinese said:
Here is what I believe is the mathematical representation you seek
I'll take a look.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #48
mattt said:
1. What I mean is that in the case where biphoton1,2 is created and photon1 is measured (and destroyed) before (for all possible reference frames) biphoton3,4 is created, there can be no biphoton1,4 Bell State (or any biphoton1,4 state).

2. I must conclude that you (and possibly the authors of that paper) are using these English words with a different meaning than the usual mathematical meaning.
1. They say exactly the opposite, using nearly identical wording as you: "When the two photons of time τ (photons 2 and 3) are projected onto any Bell state, the first and last photons (1 and 4) collapse also into the same state and entanglement is swapped. The first and last photons, that did not share between them any correlations, become entangled."

2. If anyone is mangling the English, it can't be me - since I am quoting. So it must be the authors. This is a peer-reviewed paper from an impeccable source.

As to the usual mathematical meaning, I present that in detail in my post #98 above. If you see anything ambiguous or out of the ordinary in terms of presentation, please present your preferred alternative.
 
  • #49
PeterDonis said:
I'll take a look.
Ok, I took a look. Here's the problem. From the 2002 paper, p. 5:

"A seemingly paradoxical situation arises — as suggested by Peres [4] — when Alice’s Bell-state analysis is delayed long after Bob’s measurements. This seems paradoxical, because Alice’s measurement projects photons 0 and 3 into an entangled state after they have been measured. Nevertheless, quantum mechanics predicts the same correlations."

My question is: how does QM predict the same correlations when the photons never coexist? The way I did it when I did the math using the Schrodinger equation in a previous thread, there are no Bell states with photons 1 & 4. Ever. Anywhere. So that analysis, while it certainly supports the claim that QM predicts the same correlations, does not support the claim that it does so by means of Bell states with photons 1 & 4--because there are no such states anywhere in the analysis. (And you have already agreed that, if photons 1 & 4 never coexist, there is no time at which such a Bell state exists.)

The 2002 paper does not give any mathematical analysis to back up the claim I quoted above. So I have no way of knowing why they think that claim is true. Is it just because the experiments show the same correlations? Or is it because someone has actually done a mathematical analysis, not the same as the one I did, that does involve a Bell state with photons 1 & 4 even though they never coexist? I don't mean just writing down such a Bell state; I mean showing how such a Bell state can arise from the dynamics even though photons 1 & 4 never coexist.

The other paper, from 2012, does a very short mathematical operation to obtain such a Bell state: it takes the state in equation (2) and rearranges it, applying a time delay to photons 2 & 4 and algebraically refactoring, to obtain equation (3), which is an entangled superposition of the 4 possible "double biphoton" states for photons 1 & 4, and photons 2 & 3. Each photon 1 & 4 state in that superposition is a Bell State. (In actual experiments, as you have said, only 1 or at most 2 of these can actually be distinguished after all measurements are made. But that's not important for what we're discussing here.)

However, this still doesn't help, because in equation (2), the paper is already assuming that it makes sense to write down a tensor product state between biphotons at different times. But this assumption is never justified by any first principles analysis. This paper appears to be depending on the other "temporal mode" paper that @Morbert referenced, which at least tries to construct a Hilbert space for such states. But there is still no dynamics; there is nothing corresponding to the Schrodinger equation or anything like it.

Perhaps the underlying assumption here is that standard NRQM, where you use the Schrodinger equation and you have a state of the system that evolves in time, is simply inapplicable to these types of experiments. But if that is the case, I would certainly like to see somebody justify that assumption and explain what should be put in its place.
 
  • #50
Morbert said:
The paper @DrChinese cites, cites this one in turn. From the paper...

Yes @Morbert, thanks for bringing up this reference. It is something of a companion to the reference I supplied, being from the same team. And is has additional detail as well.

So it turns out that the same basic apparatus can be used to prepare a variety of 4 photon states with temporal separation. Either GHZ or biphoton pairs. And various entangled states of 6 or more photons as well!

@PeterDonis: I had mentioned in post #96.e. that actually, the experiment I cite uses a single PDC crystal to produce the time separated biphotons. That is different from what might be expected, and it is possible something I said previously led you astray on this point (if you were astray).
 
  • #51
PeterDonis said:
Ok, I took a look. Here's the problem. From the 2002 paper, p. 5:

"A seemingly paradoxical situation arises — as suggested by Peres [4] — when Alice’s Bell-state analysis is delayed long after Bob’s measurements. This seems paradoxical, because Alice’s measurement projects photons 0 and 3 into an entangled state after they have been measured. Nevertheless, quantum mechanics predicts the same correlations."

a. My question is: how does QM predict the same correlations when the photons never coexist?

The way I did it when I did the math using the Schrodinger equation in a previous thread, there are no Bell states with photons 1 & 4. Ever. Anywhere. So that analysis, while it certainly supports the claim that QM predicts the same correlations, does not support the claim that it does so by means of Bell states with photons 1 & 4--because there are no such states anywhere in the analysis. (And you have already agreed that, if photons 1 & 4 never coexist, there is no time at which such a Bell state exists.)

b. The 2002 paper does not give any mathematical analysis to back up the claim I quoted above. So I have no way of knowing why they think that claim is true. Is it just because the experiments show the same correlations? Or is it because someone has actually done a mathematical analysis, not the same as the one I did, that does involve a Bell state with photons 1 & 4 even though they never coexist? I don't mean just writing down such a Bell state; I mean showing how such a Bell state can arise from the dynamics even though photons 1 & 4 never coexist.

c. The other paper, from 2012, does a very short mathematical operation to obtain such a Bell state: it takes the state in equation (2) and rearranges it, applying a time delay to photons 2 & 4 and algebraically refactoring, to obtain equation (3), which is an entangled superposition of the 4 possible "double biphoton" states for photons 1 & 4, and photons 2 & 3. Each photon 1 & 4 state in that superposition is a Bell State. (In actual experiments, as you have said, only 1 or at most 2 of these can actually be distinguished after all measurements are made. But that's not important for what we're discussing here.)

d. Perhaps the underlying assumption here is that standard NRQM, where you use the Schrodinger equation and you have a state of the system that evolves in time, is simply inapplicable to these types of experiments. But if that is the case, I would certainly like to see somebody justify that assumption and explain what should be put in its place.
I see your dilemma and acknowledge your points. Unfortunately I am not the person to bridge the published papers to your type of analysis. Without in any way taking away from your approach, I will simply point out your methodology/approach does not appear in the hundreds of papers I have read on the subject. Instead, the presentation is nearly identical in papers written in the 1999 to present time frame.

a. The answer is that QM is not only quantum nonlocal (our agreed upon terminology), it is also quantum non-spatiotemporal. Now before anyone objects to my usage of the term as speculative or overreaching, let me show you how and why this has actually been evident for many decades. Further, it really shouldn't be a surprise to anyone.

It should be clear from my post #91 that there is actually a pattern at play in the 6 experiments I referenced there. Each is a variant of separation in spacetime and order of measurement. Specifically, please look at papers 1. and 4, which I am reposting.
  1. Basic Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Zeilinger et al, etc.
  2. n/a
  3. n/a
  4. Delayed Choice Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed subsequent to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Ma et al, etc.
Reference 1 includes a Delayed Choice version of Entanglement Swapping, as does the 4 reference. In these versions of swapping, the Bell State Measurement (BSM/BSA) occurs after both the other 2 photons have ceased to exist. In terms of what we've been discussing on photons that never co-exist: Photons 1 and 4 are entangled after photon 1 ceased to exist. In the Delayed Choice permutations: Photons 1 and 4 are entangled after both photons 1 and 4 cease to exist, but they did co-exist at some time. This has actually been confirmed in experiments going back to 2002, per the references.

So if your argument is that photon 1 cannot be placed in a Bell state (i.e. become an entangled component of a biphoton) after it ceases to exist, you're also gonna need to disavow all these referenced Delayed Choice experiments - as well as of all kinds of other Delayed Choice experiments as well. Whew, that's a lot of published material to deny! Check out this 28 page 2014 summary of "Delayed-choice gedanken experiments and their realizations" by top experimentalists Ma, Kofler and Zeilinger. The basic theme: The ordering of measurements (including delayed choice) has no affect on the quantum expectation value.

All of this goes back to Wheeler, circa 1978 and after, with speculations on whether choices made mid-experiment affect outcomes. The first application of delayed choice to entanglement swapping that I am aware of is "Delayed choice for entanglement swapping" (Peres, 1999). His analysis of Bell states looks almost identical to those I have presented in various posts. He shows how the initial Product state of 2 entangled pairs becomes of the 4 Bell states. He famously said: "In summary, there is nothing paradoxical in the experiments outlined above. However, one has to clearly understand quantum mechanics and to firmly believe in its correctness to see that there is no paradox."

b. I think post #98 in its entirety shows plenty of mathematical analysis, all saying the same thing. It is normal and natural for authors to reference other works, without an expectation that every individual formula presented need be justified. I scanned backwards in the literature and found a variety of interrelated papers in the 1990's by Gisin, Peres and stuff like this.

I have never seen you demand a fraction of what I have presented so far in any thread, much less a thread in Quantum Foundations. You have asked for citations, and received them - gold ones, by any standard. All I can say at this point is: Asked and answered. Again, if you or anyone have a counter-reference unrelated to a specific interpretation of QM, then that would be welcome.

c. Agreed.

d. I think any survey of the literature is going to show about the same as what I have shown already. Obviously, the type of explanation you seek is absent. You can deduce anything you like from that. I think it is odd that in all my searching, not a single author has expressed any concerns along the lines of yours (that some key assumption is "missing" from the literature). I checked many of the references in a variety of papers looking for something like that, but they pretty much all start from the 4 Bell states. I only went back to the 90's though.



Now obviously, almost every interpretation tackles experiments like those presented in a different manner. So I am not trying to make any statement about that. But the experimental results should be accepted without question. And the description (mathematical or otherwise) of the authors of these papers should be accepted as that of garden variety QM. This is stuff that has been out there for literally decades.

So I am hoping that we can return to the discussion of Measurement in QM/QFT. What is it? Is it physical? When does it occur? What triggers it? Where does it occur? And I certainly hope that the cited experiments co-authored by a Nobel prize winner (and others equally well-regarded) can be used for discussion purposes without further debate.
 
  • #52
DrChinese said:
The answer is that QM is not only quantum nonlocal (our agreed upon terminology), it is also quantum non-spatiotemporal.
Experimentally, yes, I agree. It's the theoretical basis that I'm not clear on--but that probably means I need to do more digging into the literature. In my copious free time. :wink:
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #53
DrChinese said:
I am hoping that we can return to the discussion of Measurement in QM/QFT. What is it? Is it physical? When does it occur? What triggers it? Where does it occur?
I believe the short answer to this is "decoherence", but while the ordinary QM picture of this seems to me to be fairly straightforward, I'm not sure how the picture changes in QFT.

DrChinese said:
I certainly hope that the cited experiments co-authored by a Nobel prize winner (and others equally well-regarded) can be used for discussion purposes without further debate.
Well, the theoretical background that I'm still not clear on is not irrelevant, since any interpretation (and this thread is in the interpretations subforum) has to rely on the theoretical background at least to some extent. To the extent that interpretations can ignore the details and simply rely on the experimentally observed correlations, yes, they would not need the theoretical details I have been asking for. The question is to what extent that is actually true.
 
  • #54
PeterDonis said:
Perhaps the underlying assumption here is that standard NRQM, where you use the Schrodinger equation and you have a state of the system that evolves in time, is simply inapplicable to these types of experiments. But if that is the case, I would certainly like to see somebody justify that assumption and explain what should be put in its place.
DrChinese said:
I see your dilemma and acknowledge your points. Unfortunately I am not the person to bridge the published papers to your type of analysis. Without in any way taking away from your approach, I will simply point out your methodology/approach does not appear in the hundreds of papers I have read on the subject. Instead, the presentation is nearly identical in papers written in the 1999 to present time frame.
Do I guess correctly that Peter Donis initially did his analysis when you wanted to know how that stuff works in MWI? In that case, one explanation for the "disconnect" might be that the theoretical analysis in the papers implicitly relied on the Copenhagen interpretation, especially on the "update" of the wavefunction when new knowledge becomes available. From a MWI perspective that considers the wavefunction as something physically objective, this could feel like an invalid or incomplete analysis.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #55
PeterDonis said:
To the extent that interpretations can ignore the details and simply rely on the experimentally observed correlations, yes, they would not need the theoretical details I have been asking for. The question is to what extent that is actually true.
To give an example: @gentzen has just commented that various papers that have been referenced appear to be using a more or less Copenhagen-type interpretation. With an interpretation like that, as @gentzen says, since the wave function is not claimed to be physically real, I think it would be perfectly fine to say, look, we know the correlations between 1 & 4 are the same regardless of the time ordering or whether those two photons ever even coexist. So it seems fine to use the same math to make the predictions in all these cases. We're not claiming that there is an actual physically real Bell state with photons 1 & 4 when they never coexist. We're just saying the Bell state is the math we are using to make predictions, and that math works.

But in a realist interpretation, which would include the MWI but is by no means limited to that, the above does not work at all. In a realist interpretation, there has to be some physically real thing that the math describes, that causes the correlations. In the ordinary NRQM version of a realist interpretation, that physically real thing is described by the wave function in the math, which evolves in time according to the Schrodinger equation (either literally all the time, in the MWI, or all the time except when "measurements" or something, occur). But if photons 1 & 4 never coexist, there is never any such wave function--which means now we are stuck looking for what physically real thing causes the correlations and what math we can use to represent it, since the ordinary NRQM math with a wave function and the Schrodinger equation can't be it.

@DrChinese has, I believe, stated that he is using a realist interpretation, which is why I have been making the point I made in the previous paragraph multiple times in this thread. But I don't know whether the authors of the papers that have been referenced are using a realist interpretation or not; it's not really clear to me from the papers (and, as I noted above, @gentzen, at least, seems to think they are using a Copenhagen-like interpretation, which is not realist). So one reason why the papers don't address the questions I have been asking is that the authors don't even see the issues since in the interpretation they are using those issues are not there.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #56
gentzen said:
Do I guess correctly that Peter Donis initially did his analysis when you wanted to know how that stuff works in MWI?
You do. It was in the "Is the MWI local?" thread, which was fairly recent. I did the analysis to illustrate that the MWI does give an explanation for the correlations, but I agreed with @DrChinese that its explanation is not local, because of the nonlocality of the wave function.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #57
If we adopt a MWI interpretation of NRQM with some presentist account of time, then presumably the swap will not act on the "1,2" and "3,4" biphoton systems, but rather the the "3,4" biphoton system and the "detector environment, 2" system (in the sense that these are the subsystems at time ##\tau##, just before the BSM).
 
Last edited:
  • #58
Morbert said:
If we adopt a MWI interpretation of NRQM with some presentist account of time, then presumably the swap will not act on the "1,2" and "3,4" biphoton systems, but rather the the "3,4" biphoton system and the "detector environment, 2" system (in the sense that these are the subsystems at time ##\tau##, just before the BSM).
That would be one way for the MWI to handle this, yes. But note that in this case there is no Bell state for photons 1 & 4. The correlations would be accounted for by an entanglement between photon 4 and the "detector environment" degrees of freedom associated with the photon 1 measurement. (In fact this is more or less what I did in the analysis in the previous thread that I have been referring to.)
 
  • #59
DrChinese said:
I. Sorry, perhaps either I (most likely) or the authors of the paper were not clear. There is an N=4 photon state, but there is no tetraphoton as you mention.

b. Execute Swap: Photons 2 & 3 are allowed to overlap such that their identities become indistinguishable. You could also say that biphotons (1 & 2) and (3 & 4) are allowed to overlap.
This produces the entangled 4-photon GHZ state (2) of arXiv:1204.1997 that I was referring to as a tetrastate.
DrChinese said:
c. Final Product state: |φ+/-14> |φ+/-23>II. The paper follows standard QM predictive methods, using quantum theory (that measurement order in entanglement swaps is irrelevant to the observed statistics) that was published at least 25 years ago. Their specific hypothesis was that measuring Photon 1 before the swap (BSM) would lead to predicted violations of Bell-type inequalities just the same as if they had measured Photon 1 after the swap. That hypothesis was substantiated, yet another confirmation of quantum mechanics - and to nobody's surprise.
Yes, indeed. They showed that a particular measurement scheme applied to the entangled 4-photon state (whather a GHZ state or a product of two Bell states does not matter) with measurement at two different times produced the same statistics as a Bell state would have done.

But it didn't produce a Bell-state! Instead the first measurement reduced the number of particles, and the second reduced it again. A Bell state never appeared, and the authors of arXiv:1204.1997 never claimed that.

The authors claimed (and achieved) to show how to entangle photons to a 4-photon, 6-photon, 8-photon etc state with nonclassical measurement statistics.

They did not claim that they produced temporally entangled photons.
DrChinese said:
It was published in Physical Review Letters 110, 210403; 22 May 2013. Obviously it passed peer review.
There is no dispute about that. But publication of a paper in a peer reviewed journal is no guarantee for the correctness of every statement of its content.
DrChinese said:
Perhaps you are aware of published work that contradicts this result.
The very definition of entanglement contradicts the existence of temporally entangled photons. Entanglement requires a state in the Schrödinger picture belonging to the Hilbert space in question, and such a state always means a state at a fixed time.
DrChinese said:
So I question your evaluation of their results as "meaningless".
I only evaluate as meaningless the interpretation of their results as having created temporally entangled photons.
DrChinese said:
To summarize the line of research on the nature of measurements in entanglement swapping, which was the reason I posted in this thread to begin with:

At this time, there has been experimental verification (references below from 2002 to 2012) of the following:
  1. Basic Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Zeilinger et al, etc.
  2. Entanglement Swap with fully independent sources with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Zeilinger et al, etc.
  3. Remote (photons 1 & 4 outside each others' light cone) Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Gisin et al, etc.
  4. Delayed Choice Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed subsequent to observation of entanglement between (photons 1 & 4). See Ma et al, etc.
  5. Temporal Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed prior to observation of photon 4 but subsequent to observation of photon 4. See Eisenberg et al.
  6. Failure of Temporal Entanglement Swap with Bell State Measurement (photons 2 & 3) performed without indistinguishability** of photons 2 & 3, prior to observation of photon 4 but subsequent to observation of photon 4. See Eisenberg et al.
Hopefully, the pattern is clear: the same results are obtained, regardless of measurement order.
The pattern is clear: They measured multiphoton states at different times and obtained a statistics identical with that of measuring a Bell state. In no case, they produced a temporally entangled state, since the latter is a thing that cannot be consistently defined.

DrChinese said:
I am not aware of any aspects of relativistic QFT that would add to this discussion or lead to any predictions contrary to garden variety QM.
This has nothing to do with relativistic or not. The Hilbert spaces in question are finite-dimensional, so no field theory is involved.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis and mattt
  • #60
DrChinese said:
The first application of delayed choice to entanglement swapping that I am aware of is "Delayed choice for entanglement swapping" (Peres, 1999). His analysis of Bell states looks almost identical to those I have presented in various posts.
With the exception that he is precise about the implications. The abstract says:
Asher Peres said:
each subset behaves as if it consisted of entangled pairs of distant particles, that have never communicated in the past, even indirectly via other particles.
Note the subjunctive: The claim is only identical behavior of the statistics, not the creation of a meaningless temporally entangled state!
DrChinese said:
From HERE (my primary reference
It seems that this is the paper that coined the notion of ''entangled pair of photons that have never coexisted'', since they state that
Megidish et al said:
Previous demonstrations [...] entangled photons that were separated spatially, but not temporally, i.e., all the photons that were entangled, existed and were measured at the same time.
But they do not give any definition of the meaning of the new concept. Thus it must be inferred by reading between the lines. Clearly it means no more than pairs of photons that reproduce the statistics of entangled photons, in the above as-if sense of Peres.

Figure 1 shows that we have between I and II a 2-photon state, between II and III a 1-photon state, between III and IV a 3-photon state, between IV and V a 1-photon state, and after V a 0-photon state. These are the physical states actually present in the experiments - well-defined states at each time.

By the experimental set-up, the statistical behavior of the chain is identical to that we'd have obtained by starting with the entangled 4-photon state given by equation (2), measured in several stages to produce a temporally stretched Bell statistics for the photon pair 1, 4. Thus, in the careful formulation of Peres, the whole set-up ''behaves as if it consisted of entangled pairs of distant particles, that have never communicated in the past, even indirectly via other particles.''

Talking of temporal modes replaces the physical states by imagined (physically unrealized) states that would behave the same as the physical states, if they would have been created in place of the actual set-up and subjected to the same projective measurements. This works for simple combination schemes where such a would-be equivalent behavior can be justified, and may justify talking informally about ''temporally entangled photons'', using loose language as used elsewhere, e.g., when talking about virtual particles. It does, not, however, justify talking of temporally entangled 2-photon states or biphotons, since quantum-mechanical states are mathematically well-defined objects with a clear single time meaning.
DrChinese said:
the cited experiments co-authored by a Nobel prize winner
Who of the authors of your primary source is a Nobel prize winner? Which year?
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis and mattt
  • #61
PeterDonis said:
Experimentally, yes, I agree. It's the theoretical basis that I'm not clear on--but that probably means I need to do more digging into the literature. In my copious free time. :wink:
I still have no idea how you are able to cover so much ground... I am thinking vampire... :smile:
 
  • Haha
Likes PeterDonis
  • #62
A. Neumaier said:
1. This produces the entangled 4-photon GHZ state (2) of arXiv:1204.1997 that I was referring to as a tetrastate.

Yes, indeed. They showed that a particular measurement scheme applied to the entangled 4-photon state (whather a GHZ state or a product of two Bell states does not matter) with measurement at two different times produced the same statistics as a Bell state would have done.

But it didn't produce a Bell-state! Instead the first measurement reduced the number of particles, and the second reduced it again. A Bell state never appeared, and the authors of arXiv:1204.1997 never claimed that.

The authors claimed (and achieved) to show how to entangle photons to a 4-photon, 6-photon, 8-photon etc state with nonclassical measurement statistics.

They did not claim that they produced temporally entangled photons.

2. There is no dispute about that. But publication of a paper in a peer reviewed journal is no guarantee for the correctness of every statement of its content.

3. The very definition of entanglement contradicts the existence of temporally entangled photons. Entanglement requires a state in the Schrödinger picture belonging to the Hilbert space in question, and such a state always means a state at a fixed time.

I only evaluate as meaningless the interpretation of their results as having created temporally entangled photons.

The pattern is clear: They measured multiphoton states at different times and obtained a statistics identical with that of measuring a Bell state. In no case, they produced a temporally entangled state, since the latter is a thing that cannot be consistently defined.

4. This has nothing to do with relativistic or not. The Hilbert spaces in question are finite-dimensional, so no field theory is involved.
1. I agree with everything you say about https://arxiv.org/pdf/1204.1997.pdf , "A Resource Efficient Source of Multi-photon Polarization Entanglement". These are various GHZ states which do not produce pairs of biphotons. I believe @Morbert provided this for us to have a better understanding of the reference I have been using as to the underlying physical arrangement. Five of the authors are the same in both papers. It turns out the apparatus in the earlier paper can be modified to achieve the setup for the later paper.


2. I also agree that publication does not insure correctness of any paper. I would also say that the reputation of an author does not insure correctness.

However: the norm in PF is that a peer-reviewed paper is considered evidence of acceptance of results. Specifically: "Generally, discussion topics should be traceable to standard textbooks or to peer-reviewed scientific literature." I do agree that in this subforum, the usual guidelines are intentionally (and desirably) relaxed. But I say there is no further burden on me, but there is a burden on anyone denying those results. As is common in discussions I have with others with whom there are disagreements, I am the only one posting suitable references. Generally, others simply make statements they claim to be "self-evident". It is difficult for me to believe that, when dozens of papers say exactly the opposite of what is "self-evident".

Well, this is cutting edge and state of the art in QM. So no, it's not self-evident any longer. The mere fact my reference was published in PRL indicates it was considered novel and that the scientific community would benefit from seeing the results. The complete absence of a counter-reference written since should be an red flag that your viewpoint might require revision - of course that is strictly up to you.


3. Not true at all! They define a state of entanglement in time as:

|Ψ−>0, τab ⊗ |Ψ−>τ, 2τab = 1/2(
|Ψ+>0, 2τab |Ψ+>τ, τab
-|Ψ−>0, 2τab |Ψ−>τ, τab
-|φ+>0, 2τab |φ+>τ, τab
+|φ−>0, 2τab |φ−>τ, τab )


So that would be a precise counter-example to your claim. Their experiment provides support for this equation.


4. Agreed.
 
  • #63
DrChinese said:
the norm in PF is that a peer-reviewed paper is considered evidence of acceptance of results
That's not quite what the guidelines that you quoted say. The norm in PF is that a peer-reviewed paper is presumed to be acceptable as a basis for discussion. That is not the same as accepting what the paper says as true. Generally speaking, experimental results reported by such a paper have to be accepted as true because there is no way of checking them anyway; we just have to rely on the experimentalists to accurately report what they did and what results they got. But theoretical claims can be checked and evaluated and potentially questioned here, and often are.
 
  • #64
DrChinese said:
However: the norm in PF is that a peer-reviewed paper is considered evidence of acceptance of results.
No. it is considered evidence for discussing not a personal theory, hence in the present case it establishes only that you are not discussing your own inventions.

But correctness issues are independent of that and can still be discussed without accepting them.

DrChinese said:
As is common in discussions I have with others with whom there are disagreements, I am the only one posting suitable references.
Please cite a definition of what it means to be temporally entangled, because this is what is criticized. Simply citing the use of the term does not make it a correctly defined term.
DrChinese said:
It is difficult for me to believe that, when dozens of papers say exactly the opposite of what is "self-evident".
They use buzzwords but don't give clear explanations of what these words mean. This is a common disease in hot topics.
DrChinese said:
The mere fact my reference was published in PRL indicates it was considered novel and that the scientific community would benefit from seeing the results.
The technique is novel and useful, but how they sell it is overhyped. Peres could have done the same in 1999 but he was more careful and not susceptible to hype.
DrChinese said:
3. Not true at all! They define a state of entanglement in time as:
|Ψ−>0, τab ⊗ |Ψ−>τ, 2τab = 1/2(
|Ψ+>0, 2τab |Ψ+>τ, τab
-|Ψ−>0, 2τab |Ψ−>τ, τab
-|φ+>0, 2τab |φ+>τ, τab
+|φ−>0, 2τab |φ−>τ, τab )

So that would be a precise counter-example to your claim.
No. This is their equation (3). It contains temporal modes, hence is a fictitious state. The physical states can be read from Fig.1. Moreover, formally the state (3) is a 4-photon state, not a Bell state.

Writing down a state without a theory that gives the state a meaning is a handwaving argument intended to convey the essence without being strictly correct. It actually just asserts that the system realized behaves with respect to correlations as-if it were created in a 4-photon state.

To show that the system is in that state one would have to show that it evolved from the initial state (as any physical state does) by a sequence of applications of the Schrödinger equation and POVM operations performed by the various sources and filters! This hasn't been done, and cannot be done as the dynamics is completely given by Fig.1.
DrChinese said:
Their experiment provides support for this equation.
Their experiment provides support for no more than what Peres already spelt out in precise language: that the statistics is as if it came from such a state. This doesn't make their technique useless, but it shows that they use careless language to sell their result as more than it is.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes gentzen, PeterDonis and mattt
  • #65
A. Neumaier said:
1. ...The claim is only identical behavior of the statistics, not the creation of a meaningless temporally entangled state! ... Clearly it means no more than pairs of photons that reproduce the statistics of entangled photons, in the above as-if sense of Peres.
... It does, not, however, justify talking of temporally entangled 2-photon states or biphotons, since quantum-mechanical states are mathematically well-defined objects with a clear single time meaning.

2. Who of the authors of your primary source is a Nobel prize winner? Which year?

1. Entangled state statistics are evidence of entanglement, this is well-accepted and has been for decades. The 1 and 4 photons can be demonstrated to follow perfect correlations as well as violation of Bell inequalities, something that is a certain marker of entanglement. I guess I'll have to trot out some references on that, if you are doubtful... :smile:


2. You know perfectly well that Zeilinger is co-author of three of the 5 papers I referenced, and when he won the award. His paper that most closely resembles my primary reference is Experimental delayed-choice entanglement swapping.

His experiment is nearly a carbon copy (though his came first) of the basic premise of Entanglement Between Photons that have Never Coexisted: That you can entangle photons after they cease to exist. In one case, photon 1 does not exist at the time of the entanglement swap. In the paper of Zeilinger et al, both photon 1 and photon 4 do not exist at the time of the entanglement swap. Both of these papers were written in 2012, and in fact reference [22] of the latter paper is the former paper. Obviously, both teams are in complete agreement about their respective theory and the results. And both papers ended up in PRL.

a. Per the Zeilinger et al paper, combining their (1) and (2):

|Ψ−>12 ⊗ |Ψ−>34 = 1/2 [
|Ψ+>14 ⊗ |Ψ+>23
-|Ψ−>14 ⊗ |Ψ−>23
-|φ+>14 ⊗ |φ+>23
+|φ−>14 ⊗ |φ−>23 ].


Where:
The initial |Ψ−>12 ⊗ |Ψ−>34 state is at T=t0;
the |Ψ+>14, -|Ψ−>14, -|φ+>14, +|φ−>14 states are at T=t1;
the |Ψ+>23, |Ψ−>23, |φ+>23, |φ−>23 states are at T=t2;
and t0 < t1 < t2.

b. Per the Eisenberg et al paper:

|Ψ−>0, τab ⊗ |Ψ−>τ, 2τab = 1/2(
|Ψ+>0, 2τab |Ψ+>τ, τab
-|Ψ−>0, 2τab |Ψ−>τ, τab
-|φ+>0, 2τab |φ+>τ, τab
+|φ−>0, 2τab |φ−>τ, τab )


You can see these are basically the same, the only difference being the time at which Photon 4 is measured relative to the others. When there is indistinguishability between photons 2 & 3, entanglement is swapped to 1 & 4 - regardless of when or where they were created, and regardless of when or where they were measured. That's the general rule.
 
  • #66
A. Neumaier said:
1. But correctness issues are independent of that and can still be discussed without accepting them.

2. Please cite a definition of what it means to be temporally entangled, because this is what is criticized. ... No. This is their equation (3). It contains temporal modes, hence is a fictitious state.

3. Moreover, formally the state (3) is a 4-photon state, not a Bell state.

4. Their experiment provides support for no more than what Peres already spelt out in precise language...
1. Still no support provided for your position. These papers are from 2012, and there is nothing refuting them in the literature since?

2. I provided that definition, and then you dismissed it. :smile:

3. Yes, it is a 4 photon state: a Product state of 2 Bell states (of entangled photon pairs). The equation is described correctly as I wrote it.

4. I'm glad you noticed that point (I had too) i.e. his cautious use of language. But you have the significance backwards. Peres had discovered his novel point before experimental realization of entanglement swapping had confirmed it. His description is accurate of course, and I would agree with it today exactly as written. Since then however: A large body of theoretical and experimental work has followed. Standard terminology has evolved. That's no different than usual when novel concepts appear in published works.

But if you feel more comfortable using the concept of "statistical subsets" when discussing entanglement swapping, that's fine with me. There is no more or no less substance using that somewhat outdated terminology versus the more modern one that refers to the entangled Bell state directly. So in those terms, I would state: The statistics of subsets of 4 fold coincidences do not change when measurement order of the 4 photon detectors change.

Per "Delayed choice for entanglement swapping", Peres (1999): "The joint state of a pair of singlets can thus be written as

|Ψ−>A ⊗ |Ψ−>B = (
|Ψ+>E ⊗ |Ψ+>
-|Ψ−>E ⊗ |Ψ−>
-|φ+>E ⊗ |φ+>
+|φ−>E ⊗ |φ−> ) / 2

where the subscript E refers to the particles that are sent to Eve, and the symbols Φ± andΨ± without a subscript refer to the particles that Alice and Bob keep."


So this is exactly the same mathematical description. And he explicitly says that violating a Bell inequality (in this case CHSH) is evidence of entanglement: "Thus, in each subset, one of the following CHSH inequalities is violated... In other words, Alice and Bob find experimentally that each one of the four post selected subsets produces statistical results identical to those arising from maximally entangled pairs. ... There can be no doubt that the particles that were independently produced and tested by Alice and Bob were [initially] uncorrelated and therefore unentangled. ... Later, they will learn from Eve that a definite subset of her experiments ascertained the existence of a definite entangled state of their particles." Not "as if" as you imply. The entangled state is definite and certain.

And yet again, Peres' famous words: "In summary, there is nothing paradoxical in the experiments outlined above. However, one has to clearly understand quantum mechanics and to firmly believe in its correctness to see that there is no paradox." Believe it, there is no paradox here to object to. A more comprehensive definition for Bell entangled states is required which includes temporal entanglement, just as Peres showed us in 1999.
 
  • #67
I don't dispute any of the results of those experiments. Just the wording.

In the case where photon1 is destroyed (for all observers) before photon4 is created, having "entanglement-like statistics" is not the same as having "a biphoton1,4 entangled state at a fixed time t_0" (because the latter cannot exist in this case).

If you (or others) want to call that situation "photon1 and photon4 are 'temporarily entangled' " you are free to use those words, but still there isn't any biphoton1,4 state (let alone entangled biphoton1,4 state) in that case.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn
  • #68
PeterDonis said:
That's not quite what the guidelines that you quoted say. The norm in PF is that a peer-reviewed paper is presumed to be acceptable as a basis for discussion. That is not the same as accepting what the paper says as true. Generally speaking, experimental results reported by such a paper have to be accepted as true because there is no way of checking them anyway; we just have to rely on the experimentalists to accurately report what they did and what results they got. But theoretical claims can be checked and evaluated and potentially questioned here, and often are.

The guidelines are both as you say and as I quoted; and you are correct that experimental results "have to be accepted as true". Certainly, each person will decide for themselves the significance of those results. On the other hand, there are obvious conclusions to be drawn from some experiments, and certainly I'd give weight to such conclusions when there is no contrary theoretical reason not to accept the conclusion.

And as I keep saying: If my references make claims that violate theory (which they don't, see post #118, point 4), where is the reference paper stating such theory? More importantly: when was such paper written? Was it before or after the experiment was published? Because the experiment may lead to a revision in theory (although in the case of these experiments, that isn't necessary since theory hasn't changed at least since 1999).
 
  • #69
Peres considers states to be fictitious abstractions "characterized by the probabilities of the various outcomes of every conceivable test". This is a double-edged sword for Megidish et al. It lets us make sense of equation (3), but works against their account here:
This result was described by Einstein as ”spooky action at a distance”. In the scenario we present here, measuring the last photon affects the physical description of the first photon in the past, before it has even been measured. Thus, the ”spooky action” is steering the system’s past. Another point of view that one can take is that the measurement of the first photon is immediately steering the future physical description of the last photon. In this case, the action is on the future of a part of the system that has not yet been created.
This account might be consistent, but is not insisted upon us by equation (3).
 
  • #70
Their wording violates theory (QM) depending on how you interpret it (their wording :-) ).

If you interprete it as saying: "there exists a fixed time t_0 and a biphoton1,4 entangled state at t_0", then this interpretation of their wording violates the theory (in the specific case I am talking about all the time).

But that's obviously not what they mean.

What they mean is what I (and Peter and Arnold) are saying once and again, that in that case, photon1 and photon4 satisfy entanglement-like statistics, and this does not violate the theory :-)
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis

Similar threads

Replies
5
Views
323
Replies
0
Views
1K
Replies
62
Views
3K
Replies
139
Views
8K
Replies
37
Views
3K
Replies
73
Views
7K
Replies
45
Views
5K
Back
Top