Why the Quantum | A Response to Wheeler's 1986 Paper - Comments

In summary, Greg Bernhardt discusses the quantum weirdness in EPR-type experiments and how it is due to a combination of conservation laws and the discreteness of measurement results. However, there seems to be something else going on in EPR, such as a collapse-like assumption. In trying to understand this, he arrives at the quantum probabilities for anti-correlated spin-1/2 particles, which uniquely produce the maximum deviation from the CHSH-Bell inequality, known as the Tsirelson bound. This conservation of angular momentum is conserved on average from either Alice or Bob's perspective. In contrast, in classical physics there is a definite direction for angular momentum, and neither Alice nor Bob should align their measurements with it.
  • #71
vanhees71 said:
What else than measurement results should any physical theory describe? Physics is about objectively observables facts of nature. It's not an empty mathematical game of thought, where you solve Schrödinger's equation just for fun without needing any "meaning" of the wave function, i.e., just because for some reason you like the puzzle to solve the equation.

It's sort of funny that you simultaneously denigrate philosophy and take such strong philosophical positions.

But what you said doesn't change the fact that QM in the minimalist interpretation must make a distinction between measurements and other interactions. I'm just pointing out that you previously claimed that no such split is necessary.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
vanhees71 said:
What else than measurement results should any physical theory describe? Physics is about objectively observables facts of nature. It's not an empty mathematical game of thought, where you solve Schrödinger's equation just for fun without needing any "meaning" of the wave function, i.e., just because for some reason you like the puzzle to solve the equation.

A theory of physics does not have to be based on measurements in order to have observational content. What you need for empirical content to a theory are correspondences: Such and such phenomenon described in the theory is assumed to correspond to such and such observation. You need for the theory to show how observations are affected by the objects and fields and so forth in the theory.

If human beings and measurement devices are physical objects described by the theory, then you should be able, in principle, to predict what happens to humans or measurement devices in this or that circumstance. That gives empirical content to the theory.

In every other theory besides quantum mechanics--special relativity, general relativity, electromagnetism, Newtonian mechanics, etc.--what is described is the behavior of particles and fields. That is enough to have empirical content if we (and our measuring devices) are ourselves made up out of those particles and fields.
 
Last edited:
  • #73
stevendaryl said:
It's sort of funny that you simultaneously denigrate philosophy and take such strong philosophical positions.

But what you said doesn't change the fact that QM in the minimalist interpretation must make a distinction between measurements and other interactions. I'm just pointing out that you previously claimed that no such split is necessary.
It's not philosophy, it's physics. I just take what my experimental colleagues do in the lab and try to make sense of quantum mechanics. The main difficulty in understanding quantum mechanics is that it is formulated by people who are too philosophical (Bohr, Heisenberg), and that it is very hard to get rid of their "doctrine" (as Einstein rightfully called it).

There is no distinction between measurements and other interactions. The interaction of a particle, say a pion, with a silicon chip within a detector at the LHC is just according to the interactions described by the Standard Model (usually it's of course the electromagnetic interaction for detecting particles or photons). There's not the slightest hint that there are different laws for the interaction of a pion with some semiconductor if it's used to detect the particle or with the same piece of matter if it's not used to detect the particle.

Again, you always claim that you need a split, but you never tell why you think so. Mostly this misconception comes about, because it's somehow diffused into the teaching of QT through taking Bohr et al as the authorities having the final word on the interpretation of QT, but that's not an argument at all. There is no evidence for such a "cut" by any modern experiment, as far as I know, or do you know any experimental evidence, published in a serious peer-reviewed journal, which claims to prove that there's distinction between interactions of particles with matter (i.e., many-body quantum systems) depending on whether this matter is used as a detector or whether it's not used as such? I'd be very surprised, to say the least ;-).
 
  • #74
vanhees71 said:
It's not philosophy, it's physics.

No, it's philosophy.

There is no distinction between measurements and other interactions

That might be your belief, but it isn't consistent with the axioms of quantum mechanics in the minimalist interpretation.
 
  • #75
vanhees71 said:
Again, you always claim that you need a split, but you never tell why you think so.

I'm saying that the minimal interpretation already has that split. Try formulating the probabilistic predictions of the minimalist interpretation without mentioning "measurement".
 
  • #76
vanhees71 said:
It's not philosophy, it's physics.
No, it is philosophy. It is stunning to hear a experimentalist pretend that his lab is made of quantum object and quantum observation. Every single one of your observation is classic, in the only un-philosophically possible sense.

vanhees71 said:
I just take what my experimental colleagues do in the lab and try to make sense of quantum mechanics.
By counting classical "up" "down", not by observing some weird superposition. And you fail to recognize you have a cut of how many of those "identically prepared state" you'll have to classically observe before being content with the stochastic prediction.
 
  • #77
stevendaryl said:
I'm saying that the minimal interpretation already has that split. Try formulating the probabilistic predictions of the minimalist interpretation without mentioning "measurement".

If you want to treat a measurement as just another interaction, then you should be able to formulate the probabilistic predictions of quantum mechanics without mentioning the word "measurement".

One attempt might be the following: We say that system ##A## (the measuring device) measures a property of a second system, ##B## if the interaction between the two systems causes an irreversible change in the state of system ##A## such that distinct values of the property of system ##B## reliably lead to macroscopically distinguishable states of system ##A##. This definition of "measurement" seems to necessarily involve distinguish macroscopic properties from microscopic properties.

Of course, there are alternative interpretations, but the minimal interpretation seems to me to absolutely require such a distinction. You cannot make sense of the minimalist interpretation without this distinction (or something equivalent: macroscopic versus microscopic, irreversible versus reversible, measurement versus non-measurement).

I don't have a proof that it is impossible to make sense of Born probabilities without making such a distinction, I'm just claiming that the minimalist interpretation does not do so.
 
  • #78
stevendaryl said:
I'm saying that the minimal interpretation already has that split. Try formulating the probabilistic predictions of the minimalist interpretation without mentioning "measurement".
Sigh. It is really difficult to make this simple argument. Of course, I have to mention measurments. I have to state it, because physics is about measurements. What else should it be about? I never have to use the word "classical" in all these definitions. That's the point, not to avoid the word "measurement" or "observation". Again, where is, in your opinion, the necessity to invoke classical arguments here? You havent's defined, what you mean by "classically observe".

Let's take a photon. It's observed by letting it interact with a detector (in former days a photo plate, nowadays some electronic detector like a CCD). There's not the slightest hint that the interaction of the photon with the photo plate or CCD cam is any different from the electromagnetic interactions described by QED.
 
  • #79
stevendaryl said:
One attempt might be the following: We say that system ##A## (the measuring device) measures a property of a second system, ##B## if the interaction between the two systems causes an irreversible change in the state of system ##A## such that distinct values of the property of system ##B## reliably lead to macroscopically distinguishable states of system ##A##. This definition of "measurement" seems to necessarily involve distinguish macroscopic properties from microscopic properties.
Sure, but the classical describability of macroscopic properties is not due to some cut, beyond which quantum theory isn't valid anymore, but it's explanable by coarse graining from quantum many-body systems.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #80
vanhees71 said:
Sigh. It is really difficult to make this simple argument. Of course, I have to mention measurments. I have to state it, because physics is about measurements. What else should it be about?

That is not the truth. Newtonian physics is not formulated in terms of measurements. Neither is any other theory of physics besides the minimal interpretation. What you're saying is just not true. You're interpreting things through your personal philosophy.

What all theories of physics must have (if they are supposed to be fundamental) is a correspondence between observations and phenomena described in the theory. If you have a theory of light, then for it to have observational content, you need something along the lines of the assumption that seeing involves light entering our eyes and registering with sensors there. But the theory of light is not expressed in terms of observations. Maxwell's equations do not mention observations. Newton's laws don't mention observations. General Relativity doesn't mention observations. You don't need for a theory to be about measurements in order to have empirical content, you need to be able to describe how the phenomena described by the theory affects what is observable.

That's the point, not to avoid the word "measurement" or "observation". Again, where is, in your opinion, the necessity to invoke classical arguments here? You havent's defined, what you mean by "classically observe".

I didn't mention the word "classical" either. I said that the probabilistic predictions of QM (at least in the minimal interpretation---things are different in the Bohmian interpretation and the consistent histories interpretation and the many-worlds interpretation) depend on a distinction between "measurement" and other interactions.
 
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost
  • #81
vanhees71 said:
Sure, but the classical describability of macroscopic properties is not due to some cut, beyond which quantum theory isn't valid anymore, but it's explanable by coarse graining from quantum many-body systems.

No, coarse-graining doesn't explain anything. It's another way of formulating the split.
 
  • #82
Of course, Newtonian physics is about measurements. To write down a position vector you already need to define it in terms of measurable quantities, e.g., the three Cartesian coordinates with respect to an appropriate reference frame (provided, e.g., by three rigid rods of unit length put together at a point or the edges in one corner of your lab, etc.). Physics is about measurable quantities.

Again you only stated that the minimal interpretation depends on a distinction between measurement and other interactions, but you did not tell WHAT difference this might be and why this distinction is even NECESSARY.
 
  • #83
stevendaryl said:
. That is not the truth. Newtonian physics is not formulated in terms of measurements. Neither is any other theory of physics besides the minimal interpretation..
All theories are written to express the outcomes of measurements ( or observations). It is not stated explicitly because it is obvious. J J Gleason identifies any formula that gives the value of a classical outcome as an operator, in analogy with QT. The insistence that 'measurement' is somehow different from other interactions is not justified.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #84
stevendaryl said:
No, coarse-graining doesn't explain anything. It's another way of formulating the split.
Ok, if you think so, I've to accept it, but then how can you explain the classical behavior of macroscopic objects from quantum theory at all, or are you really thinking, there's a cut on a fundamental level? If so, where's the empirical evidence for it?
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #85
vanhees71 said:
Of course, Newtonian physics is about measurements.

No, it is not. Certainly not in the sense that QM is about measurements. Newtonian physics is about the motion of particles under the influence of forces. The connection with measurement requires an assumption that the forces and/or particle motions have an affect on the measuring device. So what Newtonian physics says about measurement is derivable from Newtonian physics (possibly with other assumptions). It is not cooked into Newtonian physics.

If you assume that a spring deforms in a linear way when a force is applied to one end, then the spring can be used for measurement of forces. But it would be a mistake to define force in terms of the deformation of springs.
 
  • #86
vanhees71 said:
Ok, if you think so, I've to accept it, but then how can you explain the classical behavior of macroscopic objects from quantum theory at all, or are you really thinking, there's a cut on a fundamental level? If so, where's the empirical evidence for it?

I'm saying that the minimalist interpretation of quantum mechanics makes a distinction between measurement interactions and other interactions. I'm not saying that it is impossible to come up with an interpretation of quantum mechanics that doesn't rely on such a split, only that your preferred interpretation requires it.

Let's suppose that we have a device that measures the spin of an electron along the z-axis as follows:
  • If the electron is spin-up, a pointer on the device will point to the left.
  • If the electron is spin-down, a pointer on the device will point to the right.
If you treat the pointer like a quantum-mechanical object, then you would have to conclude:
  • If the electron is in a superposition of spin-up and spin-down, then the pointer will later be in a superposition of pointing left and pointing right. (Or more accurately, the entire universe will be in a superposition of a state in which the pointer points to the left and one in which the pointer points to the right).
But the Born rule says something different:
  • If the electron is in a superposition of spin-up and spin-down, then the pointer will later either point left, with such-and-such probability, or point right, with such-and-such probability.
That rule is unlike anything you would say about microscopic systems.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes eloheim and Physics Footnotes
  • #87
stevendaryl said:
I wasn't giving my opinion about it---I was describing the orthodox interpretation of quantum mechanics, which is that the probabilities in quantum mechanics are probabilities of measurement results.

An alternative interpretation which I think is empirically equivalent is to forget about measurements, and instead think of QM as a stochastic theory for macroscopic configurations. What I think is nice about this approach is that it doesn't single out measurements, and it doesn't require the assumption that a measurement always gives an eigenvalue of the operator corresponding to the observable being measured. It doesn't require observers, so you can apply QM to situations like distant stars where there are no observations. On the other hand, it's got the same flaw as the orthodox interpretation, in that it requires a macroscopic/microscopic distinction.

Getting back to your specific comment, I'm not sure what you mean by "naturally falling into eigenstates". Could you elaborate?
by naturally I just meant without measurement.
 
  • #88
stevendaryl said:
No, coarse-graining doesn't explain anything. It's another way of formulating the split.
Can you expand that ? It might help to understand what the 'split' actually is.
 
  • #89
lavinia said:
by naturally I just meant without measurement.

But under what circumstances would a star or whatever naturally make a transition into an eigenstate of some operator?
 
  • #90
Mentz114 said:
Can you expand that ? It might help to understand what the 'split' actually is.

I sketched this in another post a while back.

But let's suppose that coarse-graining can be mathematically defined in terms of projection operators. Let ##|\psi\rangle## be the state of the complete system (environment plus measuring devices plus observers plus ...). Then we want a set of projection operators ##\Pi_j## such that:
  • If the system is in a definite coarse-grained state ##j##, then ##\Pi_j |\psi\rangle = |\psi\rangle##.
  • If the system is in a definite coarse-grained state ##k## different from ##j##, then ##\Pi_j |\psi\rangle = 0##.
Then the Born rule can be formulated as: The probability of the system being in coarse-grained state ##j## is given by:

##P(j) = \langle \psi|\Pi_j|\psi \rangle##

So the Born rule applies to coarse-grained projection operators.

The usual Born rule can be derived from this one. The usual formulation says that if you measure a property of a subsystem, then you will get an eigenvalue, with probabilities given by the square of the amplitude corresponding to the decomposition of the subsystem state into eigenstates. But if you interpret "measurement" as meaning: "A process whereby the value of the microscopic quantity is amplified to make a macroscopic difference", then different values of the microscopic property will lead to different coarse-grained states of the measurement device.So the Born rule on coarse-grained states implies that you will get results with the right probabilities.

But note: To have agreement with observation, you only need the Born rule to apply to coarse-grained projections, not to arbitrary (microscopic) projections. And furthermore, I don't know of a way to consistently extend the Born rule in terms of projections to microscopic properties. I don't think there is any way.

So the Born rule in my understanding requires a distinction between macroscopic coarse-grained descriptions (where the rule applies) and microscopic descriptions (where it does not).
 
  • #91
stevendaryl said:
I sketched this in another post a while back.

[..]

So the Born rule in my understanding requires a distinction between macroscopic coarse-grained descriptions (where the rule applies) and microscopic descriptions (where it does not).
Thanks ! I think Sewell and some of the refs therein have something about this. I will reply ( if this thread is dead I'll start a new one).

[Edit]
@stevendaryl
This a huge subject but some re-readings suggest that if the coarse graining results in a big system that has the same eigenstates as the small grained system, then the Born rule applies to both.

(I found this fun paper which is not relevant but short and interesting)
Coarse graining: lessons from simple examples
https://arxiv.org/pdf/physics/0101077.pdf
 
Last edited:
  • #92
vanhees71 said:
The "wave function" is a probability amplitude by definition (within the standard minimal interpretation). Thus it's probabilistic from the very beginning, without any necessity to introduce classical concepts.

A probability distribution itself is classical statistical concept, involving no uncertainties. At this level quantum mechanics is just a deterministic theory as is Newtons mechanics.

The laws of quantum theory deductively infers distribution of events, given a preparation. So the heart of the predictions is at the level of distributions.

Its just the link to single outcomes that is probabilistic. But this link, depends on a definite distribution; which IMO is anchored in the observer part of the system. And the reason this is considered to be in the realm of classical mechanics is that intercommunication within the measurment device is considered trivial in comparasion. One effectively assumes that (if we forget about relativity for a second) that all classical observers are equivalent, and thus we attain objectivity. But this objectivity (observer equivalent) only is manifested in the classical realm.

Ie. without a classical context for the measuremnt device, you can not defined a definite distribution, and not even a certain probability. Then even the probability gets "undertain", in an uncontrollable way.

/Fredrik
 
  • #93
vanhees71 said:
There is no distinction between measurements and other interactions.

In the way i am sure you mean it i fully agree.

But the distinction is in its description; and the description (and the expectations) are encoded in the observer part. The "questions asked" about an subatomic system, are in a deep way "formulated" and encoded physically in the observing system. The computational inference machinery required, for constructing questions (ie. observations) live in the observer part of the cut in my view.

If we relax this (which takes us beyond the standard theory) things become very complicated. Its to avoid this we need the "classical reference". Of course my opinon is that at some point we need to face these problems, but that is exactly the questions we need to ask to go beyond QM as it stands, to understand QG and unification imo.

/Fredrik
 
  • #94
lavinia said:
Why aren't there situations where quantum states are naturally falling into eigenstates of some operator - without measurement - for instance on a star?
This could happen trillions of times and thus a probability distribution. Or is any time a quantum states projects onto an eigen state of an operator a measurement by definition?

This is not standard quantum mechanics. This is what is proposed in attempts to solve the measurement problem such as the physical collapse theories like GRW. Although vanhees71 is an expert on quantum field theory, in these fundamental and basic points, he is in contradiction to almost all standard textbooks of quantum physics.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #95
I am not! If you read the physics content of all standard textbooks, all there is predicted are probabilities for the outcome of measurements, and these predictions are in excellent agreement with all experiments done so far. That's the core of quantum theory, and that's the physics described by it. It's called the minimal statistical interpretation, and it's within the Copenhagen class of interpretation, taken away the unnecessary problematic parts, i.e., the collapse (in contradiction with relativistic space-time structure and causality) and a quantum-classical cut, which nobody has ever been able to demonstrate experimentally. To the contrary, the more advanced (quantum) engineering gets, the larger systems can be prepared in states that behave "quantum like" not "classical like", although the common "classical-like states" of everyday matter around us is of course also a quantum state. Classical physics is a limit for classical behavior of macroscopic properties which are coarse-grained quantities that averaged over many microscopic degrees of freedom. The rest is the math of the central-limit theorem of standard probability theory.
 
  • #96
vanhees71 said:
I am not! If you read the physics content of all standard textbooks, all there is predicted are probabilities for the outcome of measurements, and these predictions are in excellent agreement with all experiments done so far. That's the core of quantum theory, and that's the physics described by it. It's called the minimal statistical interpretation, and it's within the Copenhagen class of interpretation, taken away the unnecessary problematic parts, i.e., the collapse (in contradiction with relativistic space-time structure and causality) and a quantum-classical cut, which nobody has ever been able to demonstrate experimentally. To the contrary, the more advanced (quantum) engineering gets, the larger systems can be prepared in states that behave "quantum like" not "classical like", although the common "classical-like states" of everyday matter around us is of course also a quantum state. Classical physics is a limit for classical behavior of macroscopic properties which are coarse-grained quantities that averaged over many microscopic degrees of freedom. The rest is the math of the central-limit theorem of standard probability theory.

I'm not disagreeing with the claim that quantum mechanics makes good predictions, I'm just saying that it is patently wrong to say that it makes those predictions without distinguishing measurements from non-measurements.

Bringing up the central limit theorem is just not relevant to this question. It's a non-sequitur. It's possible (in principle, if not in practice) to treat a measurement interaction quantum-mechanically, but when you do so, the probabilities disappear. To recover probabilities, you need yet another system that is not treated quantum-mechanically that will measure the measuring device. There are no probabilities associated with a pure quantum-mechanical system. At least not in the minimal interpretation. That's why I say that bringing up the central limit theorem is a non-sequitur. The central limit theorem is concerned with probabilities, and the issue is whether there are any probabilities at all involved in a quantum system where you treat everything (including observers and measurement devices) quantum-mechanically. Invoking the central limit theorem is assuming your conclusion.

I don't see why this is even controversial. The basic assumptions of the "minimalist interpretation" only say what happens when a measurement is performed. That's very different from the assumptions of Newtonian mechanics, which say what happens when massive particles interact through forces. Whether or not anything is measured it doesn't make any difference.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #97
This seems pretty straightforward: If there is no distinction between measurement-like interactions and non-measurement interactions, then it should be possible to formulate the minimalist interpretation in which the word "measurement" is replaced by its definition---something like "an interaction between two systems such that a property of one system causes a macroscopic change in the other system". If you try to do that, you will see that the minimalist interpretation inherently involves a microscopic/macroscopic distinction.
 
  • #98
Again you simply make bold claims without explanation. To make my still unanswered question very simple: What's the (principle) difference between the interaction of a photon hitting a CCD screen (measurement device) and just some other plane like my desk? I don't see, where there should be a difference. It's all the good old electromagnetic interaction, isn't it? Of course, if you think photons to be too special (and they are special), just take any massive particle you like to explain clearly in physical terms the difference between interacting of the particle with a measurement device and just matter that isn't used as a measurement device.

To be honest, I think it's ridiculous to think that there are different laws for this interaction simply because once the material is used as a measurement apparatus and the other time it's not. The very design of any physical measurement device (starting from something as simple as a yardstick up to the most complicated high-accuracy devices used for high-precision measurements in (sub-)atomic physics) are based on the fundamental laws of physics, which are believed to hold true universally and do not have exception only because something is used as a measurement device. There's even no different physical law for things living or non-living. There's no "vis viva" but just the fundamental interactions of physics at work also in living organisms. This is just another example for claims in the past that physical laws might not be universal. It's one of the great achievements of science to find universal laws. Although being far from trivial to exist, all quantitative and qualitative experience shows this universality.
 
  • #99
vanhees71 said:
Again you simply make bold claims without explanation.

I'm not making a claim---I'm pointing out that what you are claiming is just not true. The minimalist interpretation makes a distinction between a measurement and other kinds of interactions. It's right there in the definition of how the wave function is interpreted. I'm not making a claim about quantum mechanics; it's certainly possible that there could be an interpretation that doesn't make such a distinction (maybe Many-Worlds, or maybe Bohmian). But that isn't the minimalist interpretation.

To make my still unanswered question very simple: What's the (principle) difference between the interaction of a photon hitting a CCD screen (measurement device) and just some other plane like my desk? I don't see, where there should be a difference

I agree. There shouldn't be a difference. But the minimalist interpretation requires a difference. So the minimalist interpretation is unsatisfactory for that reason. It's fine as a rule of thumb, but it can't be literally true.
 
  • #100
It's really hard to discuss with people making claims without explaining them sufficiently so that a simple-minded physicist can follow. Now you claim again that the minimal statistical interpretation requires a difference, and again I ask, which difference that might be! I've really no clue, and I'm curious about the answer!
 
  • #101
In the minimalist interpretation, a measurement plays two different roles:
  1. It's a physical interaction between a small system and a larger system. Presumably this interaction is describable by quantum mechanics.
  2. It serves to pick out a basis.
Quantum amplitudes are not probabilities until a basis is chosen. You cannot (or at least, I've never seen it done) make sense of amplitudes as probabilities without picking a basis. It's the second role of a measurement that distinguishes measurements from other interactions.
 
  • #102
vanhees71 said:
It's really hard to discuss with people making claims without explaining them sufficiently so that a simple-minded physicist can follow.

That's my complaint about what you have said with regard to the minimalist interpretation. They make no sense to me. You have a theory whose assumptions explicitly mention measurement, and then you claim that there is nothing special about measurement. That seems like you're contradicting yourself.

Maybe there is a way to resolve the contradiction, but the minimal interpretation certainly doesn't.
 
  • #103
vanhees71 said:
It's really hard to discuss with people making claims without explaining them sufficiently so that a simple-minded physicist can follow. Now you claim again that the minimal statistical interpretation requires a difference, and again I ask, which difference that might be! I've really no clue, and I'm curious about the answer!

Please state the assumptions of the minimalist interpretation without using the words measurement or macroscopic or observer. Until you can do that, what you're saying makes no sense to me.
 
  • #104
stevendaryl said:
In the minimalist interpretation, a measurement plays two different roles:
  1. It's a physical interaction between a small system and a larger system. Presumably this interaction is describable by quantum mechanics.
  2. It serves to pick out a basis.
Quantum amplitudes are not probabilities until a basis is chosen. You cannot (or at least, I've never seen it done) make sense of amplitudes as probabilities without picking a basis. It's the second role of a measurement that distinguishes measurements from other interactions.
The basis chosen is dicated by the measured observable in the usual way (eigenstates of the corresponding self-adjoint operator representing this observable). That's part of the basic postulates of minimally interpreted QT. At least in statement 1. we start to agree (I hope): There's no difference in interactions between measurement devices and any other piece of matter, which isn't used as a measurement device.

That the contrary is a pretty strange idea becomse also clear as follows: Suppose there's a difference on a fundamental level between a measurement apparatus and just an arbitrary piece of matter, that difference occurs as soon as the apparatus is used to measure something. So I let the measured system interact with the apparatus. At this point it's a "usual interaction" according to your previous claim, as far as I understand. Now I (or my dog or an amoeba?) decides to look at the pointer reading of the device, and all of a sudden the "usual interaction" turns to an "unusual measurement", or how else should I understand the claim? I think this view is due to some Copenhagen flavors, claiming that the mind of an observer is important part of the measurement process. In its extreme form, the Princeton interpretation, only when reading the pointer of the measurement device, the "state collapses", and this collapse is not within the laws of QT. This is precisely what's avoided in the minimal statistical interpretation, not claiming that there's a collapse or any other necessity for "extra rules for measurements".
 
  • #105
stevendaryl said:
Please state the assumptions of the minimalist interpretation without using the words measurement or macroscopic or observer. Until you can do that, what you're saying makes no sense to me.
Why should I do that, because I never claimed that this is the goal. Physics is about measurements and thus to some degree also observers (if you call a computer storage, that saves the outcome of measurements automatically an observer is your choice). The only thing I'm saying is that according to the minimal interpretation there's (a) no difference in the physical laws between situations where a measurement apparatus is used and where this is not the case and (b) that there's no difference between the physical laws concerning many-body systems making up measurement devices and any other quantum system, large or small. Of course, to make a measurement we need a macroscopic device to be able to make a measurement. I've never claimed the contrary. The only thing I'm saying is that the classical behavior of macroscopic observables does not contradict the fundamental laws of quantum theory but are well explained by standard (quantum!) statistical physics.
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
4
Replies
118
Views
12K
Replies
9
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
9
Views
2K
Replies
82
Views
9K
Replies
15
Views
2K
Replies
9
Views
3K
Replies
6
Views
2K
Replies
9
Views
2K
Replies
42
Views
4K
Back
Top