Why the Quantum | A Response to Wheeler's 1986 Paper - Comments

In summary, Greg Bernhardt discusses the quantum weirdness in EPR-type experiments and how it is due to a combination of conservation laws and the discreteness of measurement results. However, there seems to be something else going on in EPR, such as a collapse-like assumption. In trying to understand this, he arrives at the quantum probabilities for anti-correlated spin-1/2 particles, which uniquely produce the maximum deviation from the CHSH-Bell inequality, known as the Tsirelson bound. This conservation of angular momentum is conserved on average from either Alice or Bob's perspective. In contrast, in classical physics there is a definite direction for angular momentum, and neither Alice nor Bob should align their measurements with it.
  • #106
stevendaryl said:
That's my complaint about what you have said with regard to the minimalist interpretation. They make no sense to me. You have a theory whose assumptions explicitly mention measurement, and then you claim that there is nothing special about measurement. That seems like you're contradicting yourself.

Maybe there is a way to resolve the contradiction, but the minimal interpretation certainly doesn't.
I think, we go in circles here. It is very clear that physical theories are about describing measurements, i.e., quantative observations of Nature. What else should physics be about?

The measurement devices used are just made of ordinary matter and are thus described by standard quantum physics as any other lump of matter. That's all I'm saying, and that's how experimentalists construct their measurement devices, i.e., using standard (quantum) physics.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #107
vanhees71 said:
Why should I do that, because I never claimed that this is the goal.

Because if you are able to do that, that would demonstrate that the minimalist interpretation does not treat measurement different from other interactions. Nothing short of that would suffice.

Suppose I have a law of physics that states that cats always land on their feet. Does that treat cats differently than other objects? Maybe, maybe not. To prove that it doesn't treat cats specially, you should be able to restate the laws in a way that doesn't mention cats, and the specific claim about cats should be derivable from that. If you can't do that, that means that your laws are treating cats specially.

If you can't restate the minimalist interpretation in a way that doesn't mention measurement (or something equivalent) then to me, that's an indication that it treats measurements differently.

You keep saying that all theories of physics treat measurement special in the same way, but that's absolutely false. Newtonian physics describes objects and their motion and the forces acting on them. Anything you want to say about measurement follows from Newton's laws plus the assumption that the measurement device is a particular physical system obeying Newton's laws.
 
Last edited:
  • #108
vanhees71 said:
I think, we go in circles here. It is very clear that physical theories are about describing measurements

No, they are not. Newton's laws are about objects and forces and motion.
 
  • #109
vanhees71 said:
The measurement devices used are just made of ordinary matter and are thus described by standard quantum physics as any other lump of matter. That's all I'm saying

Yes, I agree that measurements can be described by quantum mechanics. But that is not sufficient for your claim that there is nothing special about measurements. Measurements in the minimal interpretation also serve as picking out a basis, which is necessary for the interpretation of amplitudes as probabilities. A non-measurement interaction does not pick out a basis.
 
  • #110
vanhees71 said:
The basis chosen is dicated by the measured observable in the usual way (eigenstates of the corresponding self-adjoint operator representing this observable).

What makes something the "measured observable"?
 
  • #111
stevendaryl said:
Because if you are able to do that, that would demonstrate that the minimalist interpretation does not treat measurement different from other interactions. Nothing short of that would suffice.
I'm too stupid to understand your demand. Sorry for that. Again: Physics is about observations of nature in a quantitative way, i.e., about measurements. All I'm saying is that measurement devices and the interactions of measured objects with them are following the universal natural laws discovered by physics, and these rules are quantum. It doesn't make sense to talk about physics at all if you don't talk about observations and measurements, because that's the topic of physics.
Suppose I have a law of physics that states that cats always land on their feet. Does that treat cats differently than other objects? Maybe, maybe not. To prove that it doesn't treat cats specially, you should be able to restate the laws in a way that doesn't mention cats, and the specific claim about cats should be derivable from that. If you can't do that, that means that your laws are treating cats specially.
That's a statement about properties of cats, and of course you can observe it and see, whether it's right or not. That cats very often land on their feet is even an interesting biomechanical issue and well investigated by physicists. I'm only totally unaware what this has to do with the interpretational issues of quantum theory.
If you can't restate the minimalist interpretation in a way that doesn't mention measurement (or something equivalent) then to me, that's an indication that it treats measurements differently.
Why should it treat measurements differently? Measurements are defined by a measurement apparatus, and the very construction of all measurement apparati I know use the known universal laws of physics. There is not difference whatsoever concerning the applicability of the physical laws to construct a measurement apparatus than any other technical gadget like a car or a smartphone (although particularly the latter also contains a lot of measurement apparati you can even use to do interesting measurements in physics classes).
You keep saying that all theories of physics treat measurement special in the same way, but that's absolutely false. Newtonian physics describes objects and their motion and the forces acting on them. Anything you want to say about measurement follows from Newton's laws plus the assumption that the measurement device is a particular physical system obeying Newton's laws.
Sure, and Newtonian physics is as well about quantitative observations and thus measurements in nature. An in principle you are right, Newtonian mechanics also is in principle the sufficient basis to construct all the measurement devices you need to measure the quantities described by Newtonian physics (i.e., times, lengths, and masses; everything else is derived). Of course, the same physical laws are needed and the corresponding theory to define what's measurable (i.e., what are the observables) and at the same time are used to test this very theory. In this sense all experimental tests of physical theories are in fact consistency tests.

Nowadays you need a lot more than just Newtonian mechanics to construct measurement apparati; at least some Faraday and Maxwell electrodynamics is usually applied. Many high-precision measurements use in fact quantum theory. The entire SI units will be redefined soon, making use of the accuracy that can only be achieved by using the properties of quantum theory. E.g., to define the second (which will stay the same as before) you use the stability of atomic transitions (or maybe in the future nuclear transitions, which are even more stable and accurate), only describable by quantum theory. The representation of the ampere will hinge on quantum effects providing accurate quantities described by fundamental constants (among the THE quantum one par excellence, ##\hbar##) like the quantization of magnetic moments, Josephson junctions, etc. etc. Classical physics is way to inaccurate to be used to define the base units of the SI for use in the 21st century!
 
  • #112
stevendaryl said:
What makes something the "measured observable"?
That's simple: By measuring it. I think we just are unable to explain to each other what the issue is. Maybe it's better to leave it at that :-(.
 
  • #113
vanhees71 said:
I'm too stupid to understand your demand.

I don't think that's true. I think that you are unable to answer because you are holding onto two incompatible beliefs.

Sorry for that. Again: Physics is about observations of nature in a quantitative way, i.e., about measurements.

I'm not asking a philosophical question. You have a tendency to turn everything into philosophy, and then state how much you dislike philosophy.

I'm asking a technical question: Is it possible to formulate the minimal interpretation of quantum mechanics in a way that does not mention measurement?

The answer seems to be no. That's very different from the case with every other theory of physics.

Newton's laws are not formulated in terms of measurements. They make predictions about the results of measurements, which is all that you want for a theory to have empirical content.

That's a statement about properties of cats, and of course you can observe it and see, whether it's right or not. That cats very often land on their feet is even an interesting biomechanical issue and well investigated by physicists. I'm only totally unaware what this has to do with the interpretational issues of quantum theory.

It shows that you are claiming two contradictory things. If my axioms mention cats, then either the axioms can be reformulated so that cats are not specifically mentioned, or else it's false to claim that they don't treat cats specially. If your axioms mention measurements, then either the axioms can be reformulated so that measurements are not explicitly mentioned, or it's false to claim that they don't treat measurements specially.
 
  • #114
vanhees71 said:
there's (a) no difference in the physical laws between situations where a measurement apparatus is used and where this is not the case and (b) that there's no difference between the physical laws concerning many-body systems making up measurement devices and any other quantum system, large or small.

But WHERE are the physical laws manifested without a classical context? In the mathematical realm?

vanhees71 said:
Of course, to make a measurement we need a macroscopic device to be able to make a measurement. I've never claimed the contrary.

Yes, but I get the impression that you might think this is not a major point, but a practicality?

Without the classical realm, we would not only have problems to make a reliable measurement, we would not have been able to reliable infer the laws of particle physics in the first place from large amounts of measurements! Without this, we could not compute the expectation values because the algorithm is unknown.

I may be taking this a step further here, but i think that the whole notion of physical law becomes fluid once we remove the classical observer. And thus fluidity may be necessary to face, but there is not fluidity in current theory, thanks to relating things to a classical measurement device. Here i think Bohr is very minimalist. He does not assume anything. He just notes that we need the classical context, to construct the questions that define the P-distributions.

vanhees71 said:
The only thing I'm saying is that the classical behavior of macroscopic observables does not contradict the fundamental laws of quantum theory but are well explained by standard (quantum!) statistical physics.

A catch is the the laws of standard physics are inferred in the classical realm. You can not first abduce statistical laws, then remove the basis for the statistical processing, and claim that you still have a valid inference. Its a fallacy.

It is one thing to in principle explain a macroscopic piece of metal from QM as a manybody problem, because from the point of view of the human Earth based laboratory both are "small". Both are relative to our lab, "small subsystems". But if we make cosmological observations, or scale the classical laboratory down to grain level, this logic breaks.

If we stay away from such extremes, and study only small subsystems - from the point of view of a classical boundary, then current physics works fine. I mainly care about this as i want to develop this. But to develp this its good to first understand the premises of current framework.

/Fredrik
 
  • #115
vanhees71 said:
That's simple: By measuring it.

I'm asking: What does it mean to measure something? Informally, I measured some property if I performed an action so that afterward, I know its value. That way of phrasing it sounds very solipsistic. Must there be a person around in order for quantum probabilities to be meaningful?

An alternative is to say that system A measures a property of system B if through interacting, the state of system A becomes correlated with that of system B and the alternative values of the property are macroscopically distinguishable. But that way of understanding it makes a macroscopic/microscopic distinction, which you claim not to be making.
 
  • #116
stevendaryl said:
I'm asking a technical question: Is it possible to formulate the minimal interpretation of quantum mechanics in a way that does not mention measurement?
It is not possible to do physics without measurements, so any physical theory is about measurements. Your question doesn't make sense to begin with, and that's not philosophy but the simple definition of what physics is about.
The answer seems to be no. That's very different from the case with every other theory of physics.
It's not different as with any other thery of physics, because physics is about measurements. Without measurements there's no physics.
Newton's laws are not formulated in terms of measurements. They make predictions about the results of measurements, which is all that you want for a theory to have empirical content.
Of course are Newton's laws about measurements, because all of physics is about measurements. You start with the postulates about space and time, which implies that you talk about measurable quantities like the period of a pendulum or a planet orbiting the Sun and about distances and angles of bodies in space. Without at least these kinematical observables you cannot even start to state the postulates!
It shows that you are claiming two contradictory things. If my axioms mention cats, then either the axioms can be reformulated so that cats are not specifically mentioned, or else it's false to claim that they don't treat cats specially. If your axioms mention measurements, then either the axioms can be reformulated so that measurements are not explicitly mentioned, or it's false to claim that they don't treat measurements specially.
What you stated is a prediction about the behavior of cats. You use (implicitly) the definition of "cat" and it's a statement about the mechanics of cats, which can be checked by observation. Of course, if you make a statement about something it's a statement about this entity. However, I don't see at all what this has to do with the foundations of quantum theory and particularly what this has to do with the existence of a classical-quantum cut (which you seem to insist on as vehemently as I deny any empirical foundation for its existence) or, for me even on the edge of esoterics, that a piece of matter cannot be described by the universal physical laws of nature only because it's used as a measurement device. Are you really claiming that a piece of wood changes to obey the known physical laws, only because I put some marks of it to use it as a yardstick? For me that would be utter nonsense.
 
  • #117
vanhees71 said:
Why should it treat measurements differently?

As Maximilian Schlosshauer remarks in “ELEGANCE AND ENIGMA, The Quantum Interviews”:

“Measurement-as-interaction, by contrast [to measurement-as-axiom], leads to an entangled quantum state for the composite system-plus-apparatus. The system has been sucked into a vortex of entanglement and no longer has its own quantum state. On top of that, the entangled state fails to indicate any particular measurement outcome.”
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #118
vanhees71 said:
It is not possible to do physics without measurements,

That wasn't the question. The question was whether it is possible formulate the minimal interpretation without mentioning measurements. Can you answer that question?
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #119
vanhees71 said:
Of course are Newton's laws about measurements, because all of physics is about measurements.

No, Newton's laws are not about measurements. They are about particles and forces and motion. You can deduce facts about measurements from those laws (under the assumption that your measurement devices themselves are physical systems made up of particles and affected by forces.)
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #120
vanhees71 said:
It is not possible to do physics without measurements, so any physical theory is about measurements.

No, any physical theory has to be able to model measurements. But the mathematical machinery of QM, the thing that makes predictions, does much more than that: it tells you, "when a measurement occurs, use the Born rule to calculate the probabilities of the possible outcomes". No other physical theory has a rule like that embedded in its mathematical machinery. Newton's Laws, to use the example you have been using, don't tell you "when a measurement occurs, use F = ma", for example. They just say "F = ma".
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim and A. Neumaier
  • #121
stevendaryl said:
I'm asking: What does it mean to measure something? Informally, I measured some property if I performed an action so that afterward, I know its value. That way of phrasing it sounds very solipsistic. Must there be a person around in order for quantum probabilities to be meaningful?

An alternative is to say that system A measures a property of system B if through interacting, the state of system A becomes correlated with that of system B and the alternative values of the property are macroscopically distinguishable. But that way of understanding it makes a macroscopic/microscopic distinction, which you claim not to be making.
That's again very easy. Measuring something means to compare the measured quantity with a unit which is defined by a real-world measuring procedure (or more precistely an equivalence class of measurement procedures; e.g., to measure the width of my office I can either use a simple yardstick or nowadays a laser rangefinder, but both measurements define the same quantity "length" of course).

Of course, on my opinion the probabilities of quantum theory do not need any human being to take note about the outcome of the measurement. I thought that's behind your insistence on the claim that QT necessarily implies that the universal physical laws do not hold for measurement devices.

Of coarse, I make this macroscopic-microscopic distinction, but I don't claim that there is a fundamental quantum-classical cut. The classical behavior of macroscopic objects, needed to make a measurement (this is one of the few things I think Bohr in fact got right), is however derivable from standard quantum theory in the minimal interpretation. It's based on using only averaged macroscopic observables of the macroscopic system, which are accurate enough to describe its behavior.

For measurement devices that's not different. Of course it has to interact with the measured object and gets entangled with this object in a way that a macroscopic pointer reading allows to uniquely read off the value of the measured observable.
 
  • #122
@vanhees71, can you at least admit that Newton's laws of motion do not mention measurements? But the axioms of the "minimalist interpretation" do mention measurements?
  1. Every object in a state of uniform motion tends to remain in that state of motion unless an external force is applied to it.
  2. The relationship between an object's mass m, its acceleration a, and the applied force F is F = ma.
  3. For every action there is an equal and opposite reaction.
None of those mention "measurement". I don't see how there is room to argue about that.
 
  • #123
vanhees71 said:
That's again very easy. Measuring something means to compare the measured quantity with a unit which is defined by a real-world measuring procedure (or more precistely an equivalence class of measurement procedures; e.g., to measure the width of my office I can either use a simple yardstick or nowadays a laser rangefinder, but both measurements define the same quantity "length" of course).

Of course, on my opinion the probabilities of quantum theory do not need any human being to take note about the outcome of the measurement. I thought that's behind your insistence on the claim that QT necessarily implies that the universal physical laws do not hold for measurement devices.

Of coarse, I make this macroscopic-microscopic distinction, but I don't claim that there is a fundamental quantum-classical cut.

I don't really care about the quantum-classical cut, and I haven't mentioned that. But you now agree that the minimal interpretation treats macroscopic interactions differently than microscopic interactions? Surely, one electron scattering off another does not constitute a measurement?
 
  • #124
PeterDonis said:
No, any physical theory has to be able to model measurements. But the mathematical machinery of QM, the thing that makes predictions, does much more than that: it tells you, "when a measurement occurs, use the Born rule to calculate the probabilities of the possible outcomes". No other physical theory has a rule like that embedded in its mathematical machinery. Newton's Laws, to use the example you have been using, don't tell you "when a measurement occurs, use F = ma", for example. They just say "F = ma".
Quantum theory also simply says ##\mathrm{i} \partial_t |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{H} |\psi(t) \rangle##. This is as empty a mathematical phrase as ##F=ma## if you don't tell what it has to do with observables, i.e., measurable quantities. The only meaning of force, mass, and acceleration in Newtonian mechanics is through measurement procedures enabling you to measure these quantities. The same holds for state vectors: Together with eigenvectors of self-adjoint operators, representing the observables in the quantum formalism, its physical meaning is through the possibility to measure this observable on an ensemble of equally prepared systems (that's the difference to Newtonian physics indeed: you only make probabilistic statements which need an ensemble to be experimentally tested). The meaning is given by Born's rule, of course: ##P(t,a)=|\langle a|\psi(t) \rangle|^2## is the probability (distribution) to find the value ##a## when measuring the observable ##A##, represented by the self-adjoint operator ##\hat{A}## and ##|a \rangle## being the eigenvector to the eigenvalue ##a## (assuming for simplicity non-degeneracy of the measured observable).
 
  • #125
stevendaryl said:
I don't really care about the quantum-classical cut, and I haven't mentioned that. But you now agree that the minimal interpretation treats macroscopic interactions differently than microscopic interactions? Surely, one electron scattering off another does not constitute a measurement?
No, I haven't said this. To the contrary I stated that macrscopic properties are emergent and derivable from quantum theory, using the universal physical laws of quantum theory.

I think we should end this discussion at this point since obviously we are not able to come to a conclusion anyway, and it's no longer of much use for any of the physics forum's readers.
 
  • #126
vanhees71 said:
No, I haven't said this. To the contrary I stated that macrscopic properties are emergent and derivable from quantum theory, using the universal physical laws of quantum theory.

I don't see how that can possibly be. The issue is that you have to select a basis in order for quantum mechanics to have meaningful probabilities. So in a sense, there are no probabilities at the microscopic level, because microscopically, there is no basis selected. And since the laws of quantum mechanics (in the minimalist interpretation) only describe how probability amplitudes evolve, there would be no such thing as "universal physical laws" at the microscopic level, according to the minimalist interpretation. So there would be no way for macroscopic properties to be emergent from microscopic laws.
 
  • #127
vanhees71 said:
Quantum theory also simply says ##\mathrm{i} \partial_t |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{H} |\psi(t) \rangle##.

No, it doesn't. It also says to use the Born rule to calculate probabilities when a measurement occurs. There is no such rule in Newtonian mechanics.

vanhees71 said:
This is as empty a mathematical phrase as ##F=ma## if you don't tell what it has to do with observables, i.e., measurable quantities.

I agree that any physical theory has to tell you how to relate the mathematical symbols that appear in the theory to the quantities that are actually measured in experiments. But, again, QM, unlike any other physical theory, does much more than this.
 
  • Like
Likes RUTA
  • #128
vanhees71 said:
Quantum theory also simply says ##\mathrm{i} \partial_t |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{H} |\psi(t) \rangle##. This is as empty a mathematical phrase as ##F=ma## if you don't tell what it has to do with observables, i.e., measurable quantities.

They aren't comparable, at all. In the case of Newtonian mechanics, you have a description of how objects behave in the absence of any observers or measurements at all. Then to make the connection with observation/measurement, you only need to make the assumption that your measuring device is a particular system obeying Newton's laws. The fact that a spring scale measures mass follows from the assumptions that (1) the length of a spring is proportional to the force applied, and (2) the force on an object due to gravity is proportional to its mass. Together, these assumptions about a scale as a physical object imply that a scale will measure mass.

The contrast with the Hamiltonian dynamics of quantum mechanics is enormous.

Yes, you can describe the measurement device as a quantum-mechanical system. You can give it a Hamiltonian and describe how the measurement device interacts with the system being measured. But what that doesn't get you is:
  1. The claim that a measurement of a property always gives an eigenvalue of the thing being measured.
  2. The claim that the probabilities for the various outcomes is given by the square of the corresponding amplitudes in the decomposition of the state into eigenstates of the corresponding operator.
So if you want ##\mathrm{i} \partial_t |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{H} |\psi(t) \rangle## to be the analog of Newton's laws, then it is clear that it doesn't work in the way that Newton's laws do. Without additional assumptions about measurements, you can't get any measurement results from that dynamical equation.
 
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost, Boing3000 and PeterDonis
  • #129
PeterDonis said:
No, it doesn't. It also says to use the Born rule to calculate probabilities when a measurement occurs. There is no such rule in Newtonian mechanics.
I agree that any physical theory has to tell you how to relate the mathematical symbols that appear in the theory to the quantities that are actually measured in experiments. But, again, QM, unlike any other physical theory, does much more than this.
No, it precisely tells you about the meaning of the symbols used in the formalism. The probabilities according to Born's rule are the physics content of the theory, and as far as I can see the only physics content. It's probabilistic, and if QT is complete (which I don't know of course, because you can never know, whether any physical theory is complete in the sense that it describes right all of the possible observations of Nature), that's all there is.

The only difference is that Newtonian mechanics (and all of classical physics) is deterministic, i.e., the notion of state is different in the sense that knowing the exact state means to know the precise trajectory in phase space (which can be finite-dimensional as for point particle systems in classical mechanics of infinitely-dimensional as in the classical field theories) implies to precisely know the values of all possible observables of the system. In contradistinction to that QT is probabilistic, i.e., knowing the precise state of a system (i.e., being able to prepare it in a pure state) does not imply that all observables take determined values. It's even shown through the Heisenberg-Robertson uncertainty relation that you cannot prepare a state in which all observables take determined values, but that's the only difference.

As long as there is no deterministic (then necessarily non-local) theory that describes all phenomena, I fear we have to live with the probabilistic description of QT. Nature doesn't ask what we like to have but she is just as she is, and that's what physicists are aiming to figure out through more and more refined observations and mathematical models and theories.
 
  • #130
stevendaryl said:
They aren't comparable, at all. In the case of Newtonian mechanics, you have a description of how objects behave in the absence of any observers or measurements at all. Then to make the connection with observation/measurement, you only need to make the assumption that your measuring device is a particular system obeying Newton's laws. The fact that a spring scale measures mass follows from the assumptions that (1) the length of a spring is proportional to the force applied, and (2) the force on an object due to gravity is proportional to its mass. Together, these assumptions about a scale as a physical object imply that a scale will measure mass.
I can just use your sentence with a little change:

In the case of quantum mechanics, you have a description of how objects behave in the absence of any observers or measurements at all. It doesn't become wrong. The formalism precisely tells you how the state evolves with time, given the Hamiltonian of the system. If there's no interaction with a measurement apparatus this describes the system without measuring or observing it.

In Newtonian mechanics you also describe the state of the system without considering measurements as long as you choose not to include the interaction of the system with the measurement apparatus.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and Mentz114
  • #131
vanhees71 said:
I can just use your sentence with a little change:

In the case of quantum mechanics, you have a description of how objects behave in the absence of any observers or measurements at all. It doesn't become wrong. The formalism precisely tells you how the state evolves with time, given the Hamiltonian of the system. If there's no interaction with a measurement apparatus this describes the system without measuring or observing it.

In Newtonian mechanics you also describe the state of the system without considering measurements as long as you choose not to include the interaction of the system with the measurement apparatus.

Except that in your first paragraph, you completely left out probabilities.
 
  • #132
vanhees71 said:
No, it precisely tells you about the meaning of the symbols used in the formalism. The probabilities according to Born's rule are the physics content of the theory, and as far as I can see the only physics content.

So according to the minimal interpretation, there is no physical content to quantum mechanics in the absence of measurements. That's very different from Newtonian physics.
 
  • #133
vanhees71 said:
The only difference is that Newtonian mechanics (and all of classical physics) is deterministic, i.e., the notion of state is different in the sense that knowing the exact state means to know the precise trajectory in phase space (which can be finite-dimensional as for point particle systems in classical mechanics of infinitely-dimensional as in the classical field theories) implies to precisely know the values of all possible observables of the system. In contradistinction to that QT is probabilistic, i.e., knowing the precise state of a system (i.e., being able to prepare it in a pure state) does not imply that all observables take determined values. It's even shown through the Heisenberg-Robertson uncertainty relation that you cannot prepare a state in which all observables take determined values, but that's the only difference.

The only difference between ice cream and sand is that ice cream is cold and sweet and soft and sand is not. In other words, there is almost no similarity.

The notion of state in the minimalist interpretation of quantum mechanics is that it gives probabilities for measurement results. You can't then turn around and say that a measurement result is just another physical property like any other. No other interaction besides measurements results in probabilistic outcomes.
 
  • #134
It seems clear to me that quantum mechanics in the minimalist interpretation makes an essential distinction between measurements and other interactions. If you take ##H |\psi\rangle = i \hbar \frac{\partial}{\partial t} |\psi\rangle## as the equivalent of Newton's laws, then those laws don't describe the two most fundamental empirical facts about quantum mechanics: The fact that measurements result in eigenvalues of the thing being measured, and the the fact that the probabilities are given by the Born rule. Those are new elements that must be introduced into the physics to accommodate measurements.

That's very different from the case of pre-quantum physics. In pre-quantum physics, there are no additional physical laws needed to describe measurement. It is enough to model a measurement device or an observer as a physical system obeying the laws of physics. Then the properties of measurements follow from the rest of the laws of physics.
 
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost
  • #135
vanhees71 said:
Quantum theory also simply says i∂t|ψ(t)⟩=^H|ψ(t)⟩\mathrm{i} \partial_t |\psi(t) \rangle=\hat{H} |\psi(t) \rangle. This is as empty a mathematical phrase as F=maF=ma if you don't tell what it has to do with observables, i.e., measurable quantities.

In order to make clear that quantum mechanics and Newtonian mechanics aren't comparable in such a simple manner, let me quote Maximilian Schlosshauer/1/ more extensively:

One way of identifying the root of the problem [the measurement problem] is to point to the apparent dual nature and description of measurement in quantum mechanics. On the one hand, measurement and its effect enter as a fundamental notion through one of the axioms of the theory. On the other hand, there’s nothing explicitly written into these axioms that would prevent us from setting aside the axiomatic notion of measurement and instead proceeding conceptually as we would do in classical physics. That is, we may model measurement as a physical interaction between two systems called “object” and “apparatus”—only that now, in lieu of particles and Newtonian trajectories, we’d be using quantum states and unitary evolution and entanglement-inducing Hamiltonians.


What we would then intuitively expect—and perhaps even demand—is that when it’s all said and done, measurement-as-axiom and measurement-as-interaction should turn out to be equivalent, mutually compatible ways of getting to the same final result. But quantum mechanics does not seem to grant us such simple pleasures. Measurement-as-axiom tells us that the post-measurement quantum state of the system will be an eigenstate of the operator corresponding to the measured observable, and that the corresponding eigenvalue represents the outcome of the measurement. Measurement-as-interaction, by contrast, leads to an entangled quantum state for the composite system-plus-apparatus. The system has been sucked into a vortex of entanglement and no longer has its own quantum state. On top of that, the entangled state fails to indicate any particular measurement outcome.


So we’re not only presented with two apparently mutually inconsistent ways of describing measurement in quantum mechanics, but each species leaves its own bad taste in our mouth.

/1/ M. Schlosshauer (ed.), Elegance and Enigma, The Quantum Interviews, Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011, pp. 141-142
 
  • Like
Likes atyy, dextercioby, Boing3000 and 1 other person
  • #136
Lord Jestocost said:
In order to make clear that quantum mechanics and Newtonian mechanics aren't comparable in such a simple manner, let me quote Maximilian Schlosshauer/1/ more extensively:

One way of identifying the root of the problem [the measurement problem] is to point to the apparent dual nature and description of measurement in quantum mechanics. On the one hand, measurement and its effect enter as a fundamental notion through one of the axioms of the theory. On the other hand, there’s nothing explicitly written into these axioms that would prevent us from setting aside the axiomatic notion of measurement and instead proceeding conceptually as we would do in classical physics. That is, we may model measurement as a physical interaction between two systems called “object” and “apparatus”—only that now, in lieu of particles and Newtonian trajectories, we’d be using quantum states and unitary evolution and entanglement-inducing Hamiltonians.


What we would then intuitively expect—and perhaps even demand—is that when it’s all said and done, measurement-as-axiom and measurement-as-interaction should turn out to be equivalent, mutually compatible ways of getting to the same final result. But quantum mechanics does not seem to grant us such simple pleasures. Measurement-as-axiom tells us that the post-measurement quantum state of the system will be an eigenstate of the operator corresponding to the measured observable, and that the corresponding eigenvalue represents the outcome of the measurement. Measurement-as-interaction, by contrast, leads to an entangled quantum state for the composite system-plus-apparatus. The system has been sucked into a vortex of entanglement and no longer has its own quantum state. On top of that, the entangled state fails to indicate any particular measurement outcome.


So we’re not only presented with two apparently mutually inconsistent ways of describing measurement in quantum mechanics, but each species leaves its own bad taste in our mouth.

/1/ M. Schlosshauer (ed.), Elegance and Enigma, The Quantum Interviews, Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011, pp. 141-142

Exactly!
 
  • #137
Lord Jestocost said:
What we would then intuitively expect—and perhaps even demand—is that when it’s all said and done, measurement-as-axiom and measurement-as-interaction should turn out to be equivalent, mutually compatible ways of getting to the same final result. But quantum mechanics does not seem to grant us such simple pleasures. Measurement-as-axiom tells us that the post-measurement quantum state of the system will be an eigenstate of the operator corresponding to the measured observable, and that the corresponding eigenvalue represents the outcome of the measurement. Measurement-as-interaction, by contrast, leads to an entangled quantum state for the composite system-plus-apparatus. The system has been sucked into a vortex of entanglement and no longer has its own quantum state. On top of that, the entangled state fails to indicate any particular measurement outcome.
That's a problem only if you believe in the necessity of the collapse postulate, which is not necessary at all. It even contradicts fundamental principles (relativistic spacetime structure) and it's almost always not what happens in real experiments. Of course, in some simple cases you can perform von Neumann filter measurements, but this also is within the realm of "measurement-as-interaction" as anything else, as far as quantum theory is considered complete (and today there's nothing known pointing to some incompleteness at all).
 
  • #138
stevendaryl said:
It seems clear to me that quantum mechanics in the minimalist interpretation makes an essential distinction between measurements and other interactions. If you take ##H |\psi\rangle = i \hbar \frac{\partial}{\partial t} |\psi\rangle## as the equivalent of Newton's laws, then those laws don't describe the two most fundamental empirical facts about quantum mechanics: The fact that measurements result in eigenvalues of the thing being measured, and the the fact that the probabilities are given by the Born rule. Those are new elements that must be introduced into the physics to accommodate measurements.

That's very different from the case of pre-quantum physics. In pre-quantum physics, there are no additional physical laws needed to describe measurement. It is enough to model a measurement device or an observer as a physical system obeying the laws of physics. Then the properties of measurements follow from the rest of the laws of physics.
Of course, besides the dynamical laws there are kinematical laws (you have to formulate first). I thought, the quantum postulates of the minimal interpretation are well-known enough, as we have discussed this over and over in the past. Obviously that's not the case. So here are the kinematical postulates again.

(1) A quantum system is defined by an Hilbert space and a realization of an algebra of observables.
(2) Observables are represented by self-adjoint operators, densely defined on Hilbert space (which implies that their (generalized) eigenstates form a complete set). The possible values of the so represented observables are given by the spectrum of these operators.
(3) States are represented by a self-adjoint positive semi definite operator ##\hat{\rho}##.
(4) The probability for finding an observable ##A## to have the value ##a## in the spectrum of its representing operator ##\hat{A}## is given by
$$P(a|\hat{\rho})=\sum_{\beta} \langle a,\beta|\hat{\rho}|a,\beta \rangle.$$
Here, ##\beta## for each ##a## label the orthonormalized eigenvectors of ##\hat{A}## with eigenvalue ##a## (of course ##\beta## can also be continuous, but that's only a mathematical detail, unimportant for our discussion).

As in classical physics also in quantum physics measurements are not described by theory but done in the lab. Of course, the measurement devices are constructed based on knowledge about the known laws of physics. How else should you be able to construct them?
 
  • #139
vanhees71 said:
That's a problem only if you believe in the necessity of the collapse postulate, which is not necessary at all.

I don't see how there is any physical content to the minimal interpretation without the collapse hypothesis. You measure an electron's spin relative to the z-axis. You find it's spin-up. Does that mean that your measurement device is in the state of "having measured a spin-up electron", or not?

I assume that it does mean that. Then you have a contradiction. On the one hand, you computed the state of the measurement device using quantum mechanics, and you found that it's entangled, and has no state of its own, but that the entire system is in a superposition of "the electron is spin-up and the measurement device measured spin-up and the environment is whatever is appropriate for a measurement device that measured spin-up" and "the electron is spin-down and all that entails". On the other hand, you see that the measurement device is in a particular state---having measured a spin-up electron. The wave function corresponding to that state is a different state than the wave function corresponding to the entangled state. You have a contradiction.

If you want to say that measuring the electron to have spin-up doesn't imply anything about the state of the measurement device, then it seems to me that you've abandoned the whole point of measurement, which is to give information about the world.
 
  • #140
vanhees71 said:
Of course, besides the dynamical laws there are kinematical laws (you have to formulate first). I thought, the quantum postulates of the minimal interpretation are well-known enough, as we have discussed this over and over in the past. Obviously that's not the case. So here are the kinematical postulates again.

(1) A quantum system is defined by an Hilbert space and a realization of an algebra of observables.
(2) Observables are represented by self-adjoint operators, densely defined on Hilbert space (which implies that their (generalized) eigenstates form a complete set). The possible values of the so represented observables are given by the spectrum of these operators.
(3) States are represented by a self-adjoint positive semi definite operator ##\hat{\rho}##.
(4) The probability for finding an observable ##A## to have the value ##a## in the spectrum of its representing operator ##\hat{A}## is given by
$$P(a|\hat{\rho})=\sum_{\beta} \langle a,\beta|\hat{\rho}|a,\beta \rangle.$$
Here, ##\beta## for each ##a## label the orthonormalized eigenvectors of ##\hat{A}## with eigenvalue ##a## (of course ##\beta## can also be continuous, but that's only a mathematical detail, unimportant for our discussion).

Yes, assumption number (4) makes a distinction between observations and other interactions. It's right there in the postulates. Yet you deny that it makes such a distinction. It really seems that you believe contradictory things.
 
Back
Top