Confused by nonlocal models and relativity

In summary: Nonlocality is an important feature of BM.3. Finally, does the conclusions in those papers prevent any attempts to make BM relativistic?No, the conclusions in those papers do not prevent any attempts to make BM relativistic.
  • #211
PeterDonis said:
Actually it turns out not to make any difference in this particular case; the operators in question commute regardless of the spacetime interval between the measurement events.
I'm not sure what you mean by the operators in question. I'm no longer talking about the operators in #152.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #212
Tendex said:
I'm not sure what you mean by the operators in question. I'm no longer talking about the operators in #152.

I believe what I said is also true of the operators in the more complicated four-qubit experiment that is being discussed.

If what you're talking about is something other than that, then you'll need to clarify because I'm not aware of any other cases being discussed in this thread.
 
  • #213
SteveF said:
Hello everyone!

Recently I saw this paper: https://arxiv.org/pdf/1304.4801.pdf ("Any nonlocal model assuming “local parts” conflicts with relativity " by Antoine Suarez).

He mentions standard experimental configuration with beam-splitters and detectors. Then he distinguishes possible models by assuming "decision" about the outcome at beam-splitters (like Bohmian mechanics); or by assuming "decision" at detection.

After that he shows that the first group of models conflict with relativity. Moreover, he uses the notion of "nonlocality at detection" as opposed to "Bell's nonlocality" etc. And this logic can be find in almost every paper by this author (especially, about the so called "before-before" experiments). For example,
-https://arxiv.org/abs/1204.1732
or
-https://www.unige.ch/gap/quantum/_media/publications:bib:suarez.pdf
or
-https://arxiv.org/pdf/0708.1997.pdf

One time the author claimed that "after the before-before experiment Bohm’s interpretation can hardly be considered a valid alternative to Copenhagen".

I have several questions and would be grateful if anybody made some clarification:
1. Somehow Suarez opposes predictions of standard QM and such models as Bohmian mechanics. I thought that at some foundamental level their predictions are the same. Did I make a mistake?

2. Suarez considers Bohmian mechanics to contain some "locality". Again, I was sure that nonlocality is an important feature of BM. What do I miss?

3. Finally, does the conclusions in those papers prevent any attempts to make BM relativistic?

Sorry if these questions are too amateurish.

Far from being incompatible, QM and SR share a deep underlying coherence. The mystery of the Bell basis states, e.g., the spin singlet state, violating Bell's inequality in QM arises from the same principle as the mystery of the relativity of simultaneity in SR. See this talk for an explanation.
 
  • Like
Likes SteveF, DrChinese, Tendex and 1 other person
  • #214
vanhees71 said:
Right, operator relations hold for all states.
DrChinese said:
LOL I said I wouldn't continue with you on this, and yet, I have succumbed to temptation. :smile:

I completely agree that there is no way for Bob to learn anything useful from Alice FTL. That doesn't change the assessment that the quantum state itself changes quantum non-locally. The original total state (which we agree upon)
$$|\Psi_{1234} \rangle = |\Psi_{12} \rangle \otimes |\Psi_{34} \rangle.$$
does not contain a subspace in which ##|\Psi_{14} \rangle ## are entangled in any degree of freedom. That outcome requires the 2 separate subsystems ##|\Psi_{12} \rangle ## and ##|\Psi_{34} \rangle ##to interact as part of the overall context.
It's hopeless. You even always switch the notation, and obviously you are unwilling to understand the basic principles of QFT. I recommend to read a good textbook on quantum optics, like Garrison and Chiao, and also a good textbook on relativistic QFT like Weinberg and/or Duncan, where the fundamental principles are utmost clearly presented.

Just once more to make it clear for those willing to understand the scientific facts. In the discussed experiment (now switching to the new labelling of the photons again), what has been prepared is indeed the four-photon state (using the simplified notation ignoring the full symmetrization necessary to describe bosons, which is not important here!)
$$|\Psi \rangle=|\psi_{12}^- \rangle \otimes |\psi_{34}^{-} \rangle.$$
Then Alice does a measurement on the photons 2&3, using a beam splitter and coincidence photon detectors. If both detectors fire from the spatial part of the pair state, she can be sure to have found these photons to be in the state ##|\psi_{23}^{-} \rangle##. The prepared initial state implies that for all these cases (which occur in 1/4 of all cases) Bob will find or has already found his photon pair (the temporal order of the two measurements is irrelevant here, which is a very important point to make the case that nothing is non-local in the interactions enabling the measurements, and it's based in the very foundations of QED, mathematically described as the microcausality constraint) in the state ##|\psi_{14}^-\rangle## either. This follows from the simple mathematical fact that the above initially prepared four-photon state can be decomposed as
$$|\Psi \rangle=\frac{1}{2} \left [|\psi_{14}^+ \rangle \otimes |\psi_{23}^+ \rangle -|\psi_{14}^- \rangle \otimes |\psi_{23}^- \rangle - |\phi_{14}^+ \rangle \otimes |\phi_{23}^+ \rangle + |\psi_{14}^- \rangle \otimes |\psi_{23}^- \rangle \right].$$
Here the two-photon Bell states are defined as
$$|\psi_{ij}^{\pm} \rangle = \frac{1}{2} \left [\hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_i,H) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,V) \pm \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_i,V) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,H) \right]|\Omega\rangle,\\
|\phi_{ij}^{\pm} \rangle = \frac{1}{2} \left [\hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_i,H)\hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,H) \pm \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_i,V) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,V)\right]|\Omega\rangle.$$
It is important to use the correct Bose-symmetrized states here to understand that the state ##|\psi_{ij}^- \rangle## is unsymmetric under either exchange of the photon momenta or the exchange of the polarizations (as a whole it's of course symmetric under exchange of the two single-photon states as it must be for photons). That's why it is particularly easy to identify this state, because it's the only one where the spatial part of the pair is antisymmetric and thus only in this state both of A's detectors register a photon. This happens on average for 1/4 of all such prepared states.

It's of course mathematically nonsense to say that a state contains a subspace. A vector doesn't contain any spaces, and that's not what I've ever said.

What I said is precisely what's encoded in the formalism above: One is able to define a specific subensemble of all so prepared four-photon states which is described by the state ##|\psi_{14}^{-} \otimes |\psi_{23}^{-} \rangle## by only taking under consideration those cases, where Alice's two detectors fire coincidently, ensuring that her pair must be in the state ##|\psi_{23}^{-} \rangle##. That's the realization of a von Neumann filter measurement.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Tendex
  • #215
PeterDonis said:
I believe what I said is also true of the operators in the more complicated four-qubit experiment that is being discussed.
It is indeed a bit more complicated and the 2-qubit tensor product Hilbert space leaves out some of the intricacies DrChinese is bringing up in the paper he linked. With four qubits there is room to make different subsystem arrangements in the product Hilbert space which is where swapping and postselection enter, and depending on which pairs of photons one picks for the different subsystem arrangements one is able or not of constructing them as either product states or entangled states. This can't be seen with only 2 spin photons.
But certainly your simplified 2-qubit model was right all along, it's just that it is too simple for conveying all the subtleties in the experiment linked by DrChinese.
In most of my posts from #166 I mixed considerations about the experiment and your simplified model and indeed were misleading in this sense and can be ignored.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #216
PeterDonis said:
But how does it change? ... This is a "non-local" change because the state is entangled: flipping the sign of the second term affects the relative phase on both qubits. But it doesn't change the expected measurement probabilities for Bob. ... the operators in question can and do change which degrees of freedom are entangled.

OK, you say there is no change to (say) photon 4's probability (your Bob) alone, which is constant at 50-50. But clearly the relevant issue is that photons 1 & 4 go from being unentangled and uncorrelated to entangled and correlated. That is a physical change to that system, and depends on a decision to act (or not) on particles on a different location (2 &3). Now of course 1 & 4 cannot be considered as independent particles in the first place, because they are each part of entangled systems with spatio-temporal extent at all times in this experiment. But that is just saying that there is quantum non-locality, i.e. spooky action at a distance*. *Some people may not like this term ("spooky action at a distance"), but I think it is fitting and it is in fact used frequently as being equivalent to the phrase "quantum non-locality". As the cited experiments show, norms of both time ordering and distance/separation are upended. I would say the adjective "spooky" is applicable.
 
  • #217
Well, as I repeatedly emphasized there's no causal change of photons 1&4 by Alice's manipulations on photons 2&3. The only thing she does is to select a subensemble (which is about 1/4 the size of the original total ensemble) based on the measurement outcome "both detectors clicked coincidently". The "cause" for Bob's photons 1&4 being entangled for this subensemble lies in the properties of the initial state but not in a action-at-a-distance spooky influence of Alice's local manipulations on her photons 2&3 at Bob's far distant place.
 
  • Like
Likes Tendex
  • #218
DrChinese said:
the relevant issue is that photons 1 & 4 go from being unentangled and uncorrelated to entangled and correlated

Yes, I've already agreed that this happens.

DrChinese said:
That is a physical change to that system, and depends on a decision to act (or not) on particles on a different location (2 &3).

It's a physical change to the four-photon system, which, as you note, must be considered as a single system. The change is usually described as "entanglement swapping" since the switch is from "1&2 entangled, 3&4 entangled" to "1&4 entangled, 2&3 entangled".

The entanglement swapping is done by a single operator--the beam splitter that photons 2 and 3 pass through--so there is no question of whether anything commutes at that point. But the later measurements on photons 1 and 4, that show the correlations between them, are two separate measurements involving two operators, and those two operators do commute.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and DrChinese
  • #219
vanhees71 said:
Well, as I repeatedly emphasized there's no causal change of photons 1&4 by Alice's manipulations on photons 2&3. The only thing she does is to select a subensemble (which is about 1/4 the size of the original total ensemble) based on the measurement outcome "both detectors clicked coincidently".

And as I have already demonstrated, the original pre-projection state is something like
|Ψ1234original⟩=|ψ12⟩⊗|ψ34⟩ (1)|Ψ1234original⟩=|ψ12⟩⊗|ψ34⟩ (1)
|Ψ1234original⟩=12(|H1V2⟩±|V1H2⟩)⊗(|H3V4⟩±|V3H4⟩) (2)|Ψ1234original⟩=12(|H1V2⟩±|V1H2⟩)⊗(|H3V4⟩±|V3H4⟩) (2)​

And the post-projection state is
|ψ14⟩=1√2(|H1V4⟩±|V1H4⟩) (3)|ψ14⟩=12(|H1V4⟩±|V1H4⟩) (3)​
And the statistics are manifestly different, so the experiment shows. You cannot produce the post projection statistics from any "subensemble" of (1) without choosing to perform a projection, which in turn transforms (changes) the system.

Now I certainly respect that your knowledge (and PeterDonis') of QM/QED/QFT is vastly superior to mine. That includes your ability to solve working problems, something that I cannot do. However, you are missing something critical. Specifically, you are far missing the significance of the papers I am citing and the many experiments being conducted along similar lines - of which I endeavor to represent to you as best I am able in a fair manner.

None of the authors of these papers share your viewpoint on quantum non-locality, and I have NEVER seen one refer to entanglement swapping as merely "revealing" a pre-existing state as you describe. While my notation and terminology are (rightfully) a subject for you to criticize, I would reply that you do not see the forest for the trees. That QFT predicts (and experiments confirm) effects that cannot be described using local-only causal interaction reasoning (or however you describe your position) is generally accepted in physics today. But don't take my word for it.

Again, Weinberg (Lectures on Quantum Mechanics): "..according to present ideas a measurement in one subsystem does change the state vector for a distant isolated subsystem... " [describing EPR steering]

Or from here: "Each of the two photons belongs initially to one of two independent entangled photon pairs (e.g., photons 1 and 4 of the entangled pairs 1-2 and 3-4). The two other photons (2 and 3) are projected by a measurement onto a Bell state. As a result, the first two photons (1 and 4) become entangled even though they may be distant from each other. Entanglement swapping is the central principle used in quantum repeaters, whose purpose is to overcome the limiting effect of photon loss in long range quantum communication. " [describing entanglement swapping]

Or from here: Photon 2 and 3 undergo a joint Bell-measurement. In consequence, Photon 1 and 4 are projected into a Bell-state despite they do not locally interact. [describing traditional entanglement creation using 4 photons where 2 are used to project into a Bell state], and
... creation of entanglement in between two photons is possible, even if there is no direct local interaction between the involved photons. [describing a setup where entanglement is created from only 2 photons that don't interact locally]

Don't ignore the message because my math and terminology is weaker than yours. If you don't like my equations 1-3 above, then read the cited papers and see for yourself. And given that, it renders meaningless the idea that QFT is somehow formulated "local only". Quantum non-local experiments require a quantum non-local theory*, hopefully everyone can see why. *Of course this has nothing to do with the various interpretations.
 
  • #220
I read both papers you cited carefully. You ignore what the authors say, not I or @PeterDonis !
 
  • #221
vanhees71 said:
I read both papers you cited carefully. You ignore what the authors say, not I or @PeterDonis !

How about this quote: "Of course there's no change of photons 1&4 due to manipulations on photons 2&3." See anything like that? :smile:

I have represented my position (which is standard, generally accepted physics) as best I can at this point. In fact, I have probably repeated myself too much already. I will leave it to the readers to make their own judgments and assessments of these fabulous and groundbreaking experiments. Consequently, I will bow out of this thread and thank everyone for their time and comments - especially for helping me sharpen my LaTeX from terrible to poor. :biggrin:
 
  • #222
DrChinese said:
How about this quote: "Of course there's no change of photons 1&4 due to manipulations on photons 2&3." See anything like that?
Are you referring to the composite state that includes the 4 photons or singling out the just 1&4 system?
The former changes but not the latter, maybe that's where the disagreement lies.
 
  • #223
Tendex said:
Are you referring to the composite state that includes the 4 photons or singling out the just 1&4 system?

You can't single out the subsystem consisting of just photons 1 and 4 because that subsystem is entangled with the other subsystem, photons 2 and 3, for part of the experiment.

The states @DrChinese has been writing down include all four photons.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #224
PeterDonis said:
You can't single out the subsystem consisting of just photons 1 and 4 because that subsystem is entangled with the other subsystem, photons 2 and 3, for part of the experiment.

The states @DrChinese has been writing down include all four photons.
Ok. And his quote of vanhees? Maybe vanhees can tell us.
 
  • #225
Tendex said:
And his quote of vanhees?

The states @vanhees71 has been writing down also include all four photons.
 
  • #226
DrChinese said:
How about this quote: "Of course there's no change of photons 1&4 due to manipulations on photons 2&3." See anything like that? :smile:

I have represented my position (which is standard, generally accepted physics) as best I can at this point. In fact, I have probably repeated myself too much already. I will leave it to the readers to make their own judgments and assessments of these fabulous and groundbreaking experiments. Consequently, I will bow out of this thread and thank everyone for their time and comments - especially for helping me sharpen my LaTeX from terrible to poor. :biggrin:
Well, thank you. You have stated your position coherently it is just superluminal influences that are hard to digest.

For me it is very instructive to see the QED approach.
There the solution is to expand the state that exists after the two pairs 1,2 and 3,4 are created (creation operations on the vacuum) using Bell state bases. The result shows that the 'final' state is already in there by preparation. When the entangled pairs are created, the result is inevitable and does not require any further interaction. The symmetries ensure that.

I used to find that unsatisfactory but now it seems harmonious.

But I am easily led by equations.:smile:
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71, morrobay, DrChinese and 2 others
  • #227
DrChinese said:
How about this quote: "Of course there's no change of photons 1&4 due to manipulations on photons 2&3." See anything like that? :smile:

I have represented my position (which is standard, generally accepted physics) as best I can at this point. In fact, I have probably repeated myself too much already. I will leave it to the readers to make their own judgments and assessments of these fabulous and groundbreaking experiments. Consequently, I will bow out of this thread and thank everyone for their time and comments - especially for helping me sharpen my LaTeX from terrible to poor. :biggrin:
Indeed, that's what I'm saying. There's no change of photons 1&4 due to manipulations on photons 2&3. All you do is to select a partial ensemble based on measurements on photons 2&3, and due to the preparation in the initial state, describing the full ensemble the so selected partial ensemble is described by the state ket $$|\psi_{14}^- \rangle \otimes |\psi_{23}^- \rangle.$$
That's indeed standard, generally accepted physics.
 
  • #228
Mentz114 said:
Well, thank you. You have stated your position coherently it is just superluminal influences that are hard to digest.

For me it is very instructive to see the QED approach.
There the solution is to expand the state that exists after the two pairs 1,2 and 3,4 are created (creation operations on the vacuum) using Bell state bases. The result shows that the 'final' state is already in there by preparation. When the entangled pairs are created, the result is inevitable and does not require any further interaction. The symmetries ensure that.

I used to find that unsatisfactory but now it seems harmonious.

But I am easily led by equations.:smile:
Well, there's no other chance to understand what's going on in the physical world than math and equations (most importantly group theory, which is the guiding principle; all the rest is just calculational techique).
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #229
vanhees71 said:
The only thing she does is to select a subensemble...

One doesn't select a subensemble, a measurement "creates" - so to speak - a subensemble. Thinking about the post-measurement situation cannot be conveyed to the pre-measurement situation.
 
  • #230
PeterDonis said:
The states @vanhees71 has been writing down also include all four photons.
Yes, and he has also been arguing about the selected subsystem of photons 1&4 that DrChinese keeps saying is affected in a "spooky" way by what happens to 2&3, so they are both singling out 1&4 but the relevant thing is doing it with the right math.
Now the only way to mathematically speak coherently about the subsystem 1&4 other than in the Hilbert space of the 4 photons that everyone agrees about is using a reduced density matrix for 1&4, and this reduced density matrix is not affected by 2&3, as vanhees says and DrChinese rejects.
My hunch is that DrChinese is clinging to the 4 photon entangled pure state when he says the subsystem 1&4 is affected by 2&3 but by definition as mentioned before the entangled 4 photon state is inseparable from preparation to measurement and it doesn't matter that the particular photons 1&4 never interacted before, they are prepared as entangled in the 4 photon entangled state.

DrChinese himself said in a previous post:

"Weinberg goes on to say as follows: "Of course, according to present ideas a measurement in one subsystem does change the state vector for a distant isolated subsystem - it just doesn't change the density matrix." Which is what I assert: A measurement on Alice's particle changes the physical state of Bob's remote entangled particle (what is observed)."
apparently mixing the mathematical sense of state vector that refers to the entangled total system(that being in superposition makes not well defined mathematically what a subsystem would be, Weinberg clearly takes an ordinary language license there) with some "physical state" that can't be atributed to 1&4 alone excep using the right math of the density matrix that Weinberg , of course correctly, says doesn't change in the same quote.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #231
Lord Jestocost said:
One doesn't select a subensemble, a measurement "creates" - so to speak - a subensemble. Thinking about the post-measurement situation cannot be conveyed to the pre-measurement situation.
See my last post. It can be conveyed as long as we are talking about the prepaired entangled state in the system of 4 photons that is inseparable by definition. Knowledge of the measurement effectively subselects information applying quantum probabilities.
 
Last edited:
  • #232
Of course, one is selecting a subensemble. That's the whole purpose of the experiment. As the authors (Jennewein, Zeilinger et al) have demonstrated, it doesn't matter who measures their photon pair first. They can even measure it at space-like separation of the measurement events. It also doesn't matter, when Victor chooses the subensemble from the measurement protocol.

The facts are the following:

The total ensemble (which Victor of course also can consider from the measurement protocol) is described by the initial state and is unaffected by the measurements of A on photons 2&3 and B on photons 1&4. Due to the entanglement between the photons 1&2 as well as 3&4 (i.e., the maximal Bell-state entanglement beyond the minimal entanglement bosons that are not in the same single-particle state) the subensemble chosen based on the measurement of A leads to the entanglement between B's photons 1&4 in the subensemble. There's nowhere any causal effect of A's measurement on B's photons. This becomes particularly clear by the fact shown in the experiment in the Jennewein at al paper, where A's measurement is done clearly after B's measuremet. All one does is to choose a subensemble.

Another very nice paper I stumbled over is

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10701-019-00278-8

However one has to read this paper such that it is about two spin-entangled distinguishable particles (say an electron and positron from ##\pi^0 \rightarrow \mathrm{e}^+ + \mathrm{e}^-## decay).
 
  • #234
Tendex said:
this reduced density matrix is not affected by 2&3, as vanhees says and DrChinese rejects.

I don't think @DrChinese rejects that the reduced density matrix of 1&4 is not changed by the measurement that is made on 2&3. He agreed with me that the measurement on 2&3 doesn't affect the probabilities for measurements on 1&4, which is the same thing.

I think what @DrChinese is rejecting is the claim that the measurement on 2&3 does not change photons 1&4, i.e., he does not agree that "no change to the reduced density matrix" means "no change at all". The measurement on 2&3 certainly changes the wave function of the system as a whole, and 1&4 are part of the system as a whole. It also changes the entanglement relationships--before the measurement, 1&2 are entangled and 3&4 are entangled; after the measurement, 1&4 are entangled and 2&3 are entangled. That change shows up in the correlations between the appropriate pairs of photons violating the Bell inequalities.

At least some of the disagreement might be just interpretation. When @vanhees71 talks about post-selection of a particular sub-ensemble, he is taking an ensemble interpretation viewpoint, in which QM does not describe individual photons or individual experimental runs, but only ensembles of them. When @DrChinese talks about the entanglement relations changing in an individual run of the experiment, he is taking the opposite viewpoint, that QM describes individual quantum systems and measurements.

I'll also repeat once more my suggestion to not use vague ordinary language but instead look at the math. The math is unambiguous, but there are many different ways of describing in ordinary language what the math is telling us, and those ways often seem like they contradict each other, even though they're all describing the same math and the same predictions for experimental results. To me that just means we should stop arguing about the ordinary language since it's superfluous anyway. But not everyone takes that view.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese, vanhees71, martinbn and 1 other person
  • #235
PeterDonis said:
I don't think @DrChinese rejects that the reduced density matrix of 1&4 is not changed by the measurement that is made on 2&3. He agreed with me that the measurement on 2&3 doesn't affect the probabilities for measurements on 1&4, which is the same thing.

Bell's inequalities and their violations are all about probabilities and ensembles so I don't know what else he might be arguing mathematically by the "spooky" change to 1&4.
I think what @DrChinese is rejecting is the claim that the measurement on 2&3 does not change photons 1&4, i.e., he does not agree that "no change to the reduced density matrix" means "no change at all".
I haven't seen anyone saying " no change at all". There is consensus about change in the 1&2&3&4 entangled state.

The measurement on 2&3 certainly changes the wave function of the system as a whole, and 1&4 are part of the system as a whole. It also changes the entanglement relationships--before the measurement, 1&2 are entangled and 3&4 are entangled; after the measurement, 1&4 are entangled and 2&3 are entangled. That change shows up in the correlations between the appropriate pairs of photons violating the Bell inequalities.
As you stress this is all change in the system as a whole, the product Hilbert space ##\mathcal H = \mathcal H_1 \otimes \mathcal H_2 \otimes \mathcal H_3 \otimes \mathcal H_4##, the system where we can have 4 entangled photons and different subsystems selected depending on the measurement setup.

At least some of the disagreement might be just interpretation. When @vanhees71 talks about post-selection of a particular sub-ensemble, he is taking an ensemble interpretation viewpoint, in which QM does not describe individual photons or individual experimental runs, but only ensembles of them. When @DrChinese talks about the entanglement relations changing in an individual run of the experiment, he is taking the opposite viewpoint, that QM describes individual quantum systems and measurements.
Again, this is a fine viewpoint but Bell's violations are about ensembles, an individual run is not relevant here except for selling pop-sci books about QM mysteries.
 
  • #236
Tendex said:
Bell's inequalities and their violations are all about probabilities and ensembles

Bell's particular inequalities are, yes. But a lot of work in this area has been done since Bell, including finding cases where QM predicts results that are impossible according to local hidden variable models, so that the latter models can be ruled out with 100% certainty by observing such an "impossible" result, with no probabilities or statistics or ensembles required. For example, the GHZ experiment:

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/GHZ_experiment
Tendex said:
I haven't seen anyone saying " no change at all".

More precisely, this:

vanhees71 said:
There's no change of photons 1&4 due to manipulations on photons 2&3.

Which, mathematically, refers to the fact that the reduced density matrix of 1&4 does not change. But the wave function does.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #237
PeterDonis said:
Bell's particular inequalities are, yes. But a lot of work in this area has been done since Bell, including finding cases where QM predicts results that are impossible according to local hidden variable models, so that the latter models can be ruled out with 100% certainty by observing such an "impossible" result, with no probabilities or statistics or ensembles required. For example, the GHZ experiment:

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/GHZ_experiment
Right.
More precisely, this:
Which, mathematically, refers to the fact that the reduced density matrix of 1&4 does not change. But the wave function does.
I thought they agreed on the wave function.
 
  • #238
Tendex said:
I thought they agreed on the wave function.

They do. But @DrChinese thinks that the change in the wave function (and the entanglement relations) is sufficient to say that something changes about photons 1&4 when photons 2&3 get measured, while @vanhees71 does not. At least, that's my understanding of the viewpoints they have been expressing.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #239
Tendex said:
As you stress this is all change in the system as a whole, the product Hilbert space ##\mathcal H = \mathcal H_1 \otimes \mathcal H_2 \otimes \mathcal H_3 \otimes \mathcal H_4##, the system where we can have 4 entangled photons and different subsystems selected depending on the measurement setup.
The 4-photon space is NOT this product space but it is the subspace spanned by all totally symmetrized (bosonic) product-basis states.
 
  • #240
PeterDonis said:
They do. But @DrChinese thinks that the change in the wave function (and the entanglement relations) is sufficient to say that something changes about photons 1&4 when photons 2&3 get measured, while @vanhees71 does not. At least, that's my understanding of the viewpoints they have been expressing.
Despite the fact that there are no wave functions for photons, of course nothing done locally on photons 2&3 can change photons 1&4, at least not instantly in a "spooky action at a distance".

Concerning my interpretation, it's indeed the minimal statistical interpretation, including the frequentist interpretation of probabilities: All that's done is to select (or even post-select) a sub-ensemble. The observed correlations (entanglement) between photons 1&4 for this subensemble is implied by the initially prepared four-photon state.

In my opinion there's no other way to interpret QT without violating the one or the other fundamental property of physical theories, particularly Einstein causality in special-relativistic spacetime.
 
  • #241
PeterDonis said:
Bell's particular inequalities are, yes. But a lot of work in this area has been done since Bell, including finding cases where QM predicts results that are impossible according to local hidden variable models, so that the latter models can be ruled out with 100% certainty by observing such an "impossible" result, with no probabilities or statistics or ensembles required. For example, the GHZ experiment:

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/GHZ_experimentMore precisely, this:
Which, mathematically, refers to the fact that the reduced density matrix of 1&4 does not change. But the wave function does.
There's no wave function for photons!

What changes is the description of the sub-ensemble based on the selection depending on Alice's specific measurement of the pair 2&3.

Also in classical applications of statistics and probability theory a subensemble usually has some different probability distribution for some of its properties than the full ensemble. There's nothing mysterious in this.
 
  • #242
vanhees71 said:
The 4-photon space is NOT this product space but it is the subspace spanned by all totally symmetrized (bosonic) product-basis states.
I don't see this, why can't the tensor product be used for the 4-photon system?
 
  • #243
Because bosons are bosons. It's a well-established fact of nature.
 
  • #244
vanhees71 said:
Because bosons are bosons. It's a well-established fact of nature.
I fail to see how the boson-fermion distinction is relevant to this discussion, we could be talking about electrons and spin instead of photons and polarization and the situation would be essentially the same.
 
  • #245
Sure, but it's important to treat the photons as bosons (or electrons as fermions) particularly when it comes to entanglement.
 
Back
Top